Paul James, 'What Does It
Mean Ontologically to Be
Author
Religious?', in Stephen Ames,
Ian Barns, John Hinkson, Paul
James, Gordon Preece, and
Geoff Sharp, Religion in a
Secular Age: The Struggle for
Meaning in an Abstracted
World, Arena Publications,
North Carlton, 2018.
56
What Does It Mean
Ontologically to
Be Religious?
Paul James
What does it mean to say that we live in a secular age? This simple
question, the first sentence of Charles Taylor’s extraordinary book
A Secular Age, is deceptively complex — and a bad place to start.1
Any approach that begins with a question that presumes so much,
and then continues without changing the terms of that question,
is bound to reach an impasse. Even when developed with sophistication, such an approach is limited either to homogenising our
time or to qualifying its big picture by tortuous (or elegant)
intertwined lineages of competing cultural description. Even if that
approach unpacks the complex phenomenology and history of the
concept of ‘a secular age’, it is bound to remain caught in an
assumption that mapping the condition of an age can be done by
first characterising the social whole in singular and epochal terms,
and then addressing the manifold qualifications that do not fit or
complicate that whole.
Responding to the problem of treating our time as an epochal
singularity is one of the tasks of this essay. The bigger task is to
1
C. Taylor, A Secular Age, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 2007, p. 3.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
57
develop an alternative approach to understanding religion and
secularity as phenomena responding to existential tensions and
contradictions across changing social conditions. This entails
thinking about what it means to live on this planet in the twentyfirst century at a time when crises of existential meaning parallel an
encompassing crisis of ecological sustainability:
I’ve stepped in the middle of seven sad forests
I’ve been out in front of a dozen dead oceans
I’ve been ten thousand miles in the mouth of a graveyard
And it’s a hard, and it’s a hard, and it’s a hard, and it’s a hard
And it’s a hard rain’s a-gonna fall.2
What does it mean to say that we live in a secular age? For all
that it is badly framed, the question tells us a lot about the modern
search for meaning. The quest for an over-bracing dramatic
characterisation of ‘our time’ has become a consuming part of that
search. Even the phrase ‘in our time’ has a parallel lineage, though
with more twists. Ernest Hemingway famously used it in 1925 to
bring together his first collection of writings. From Karl Jaspers’ The
Spiritual Situation of the Age3 and Martin Heidegger’s ‘The Age
of the World Picture’ to Martin Albrow’s The Global Age, one dominant line of analysis has been that our time, like so many others,
can be critically understood in terms of a singular overriding
characterisation or Zeitgeist — albeit with qualifications. In a
wondrous case of reductive exaggeration, Albrow argues that the
modern age has passed: ‘the Global Age involves the supplanting
of modernity with globality’.4 This move gets many things wrong,
including conflating an ontological formation-in-dominance — that
is, ‘modernity’ — with a spatial process moving towards a
descriptive state — ‘globality’. The expressive confidence of the
claim shows up the limits of such characterisations, argumentum ad
absurdum.
In a parallel process towards the end of the twentieth century,
2
3
4
B. Dylan, ‘A Hard Rain’s a-Gonna Fall’, 1962, <https://bobdylan.com/songs/hard-rainsgonna-fall/>, accessed 17 December 2017. The lyrics were written as a conversation between
a mother and her son, with biblical references, including to the Flood. In the 1970s Dylan
converted to Christianity while continuing to observe basic Jewish ritualistic practices.
Here I am reading Jaspers through Jürgen Habermas’ edited volume Observations on the
‘Spiritual Situation of the Age’ (Cambridge, MIT Press, 1985). Jaspers developed the concept of
the Axial Age to encompass the period 800–200 BCE, variously an interregnum between
empires in China, India, Persia, Judea and Greece, when in different places at the same time
‘the spiritual foundations of humanity were laid’ (K. Jaspers, Way to Wisdom, New Haven,
Yale University Press, 2nd edition, 2003, p. 98).
M. Albrow, The Global Age: State and Society Beyond Modernity, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1996,
p. 4.
58
Paul James
some writers began to do the same thing with the concept of
‘society’. Book titles evoked the coming of the technological society,
the information society, the risk society, the knowledge society and
so on.5 The obvious and serious problem with these appellations is
that across human history we have always lived with technology,
information, risk and knowledge. Yes, there is no doubt that how
we live with those phenomena has changed, and it is the dominant
constitutive framing of our time that needs theorising. However,
descriptive epochalism just confuses things. Unfortunately, in the
absence of a convincing rewriting of theory, this practice of naming
persisted. And if a writer really wanted to make a big point they
could redouble the age–society nexus. Manuel Castells’ book was
accordingly called The Information Age: Volume 1, The Rise of the
Network Society.6 This draws both tropes — age and society — into
its orbit. If nothing else, the book signalled that we had arrived at
the age of big book titles.
An alternative poststructuralist lineage came to proclaim the
impossibility of such characterisations. However, this was neither
the clear break it appeared to be nor an adequate way of proceeding to an alternative rendition of social complexity. Early in the
poststructuralist turn, an apparently modest new concept entered
the lexicon — the ‘condition’ of our time. However, as it was developed in writings such as Jean-François Lyotard’s The Postmodern
Condition, the concept carried forward much of the sensibility of
earlier reductive, epoch-designating phrases. It solved little and
added new problems. Even if the postmodern condition was a
condition of instability with a small ‘c’, the early writings of the
poststructuralists carried forward the epochalism that they at the
same time rejected. For Lyotard, the postmodern condition was
more than an ontological dominant or an emergent level of the
social that was coming in contradictory ways to remake other levels
of the social (as this essay will argue).7 It was ‘the condition’ of our
time, ‘the postmodern age’, to use his words (emphasis added). It
was the condition that cultures entered into, he argued, just as
5
6
7
J. Ellul, The Technological Society, Cambridge, Vintage Books, 1964; D. Lyon, The Information
Society, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1988; U. Beck, Risk Society, London, Sage Publications,
1992; G. Vattimo, The Transparent Society, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1992.
The Information Age is the collective title of Manuel Castells’ three-volume account of the
contemporary world, which began with The Information Age: Volume 1, The Rise of the Network
Society (Cambridge, Blackwell, 1996).
These two phrases, ‘ontological dominant’ and ‘level of the social’, hint at the position from
which I come, influenced profoundly by other writers associated with the Arena editorial
group: Geoff Sharp, John Hinkson, Alison Caddick, Simon Cooper, et al.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
59
‘societies enter what is known as the postindustrial age’.8 I have
added emphasis to the definite article ‘the’, but Lyotard might as
well have also done so. As we shall later see, this was not so
different from one of the other great classic texts of that time —
Fredric Jameson’s innovative and rich, but in the end overly
simplifying, account of postmodernism as the cultural logic of late
capitalism.9
A number of questions arise out of this discussion of the search
for an overriding characterisation of our time, including the place
of religion and secularity. The first is theoretical, the second is about
the limits of social theory, and the third is cultural-political. Firstly,
how can we find a way to understand the social whole without
reducing the complexities and contradictions of social life to that of
a singular age? Responding to this question will take us through
the problems of talking about epochs, ages, Zeitgeists and
conditions. Except when projected as provisional and deeply
qualified descriptions of a period, naming a time span in terms of a
social dominant tends, on the one hand, to downplay the consequences of that social dominant and ignore that it co-exists with
and dominates other ways of life. On the other hand, in examples
such as Ulrich Beck’s ‘risk society’ or Zygmunt Bauman’s ‘liquid
modernity’,10 naming a period tends to reductively over-accentuate
a singular dimension of the contemporary world, make that
domination singular. It then distorts our understanding of that
singular dimension. This is a complex problem from which it is
difficult to escape.
This train of thought leads us to a general proposal that lies at
the heart of this essay. The social whole can better be understood in
terms of changing intersecting levels (or assemblages) of
ontological formations — life-ways formed in tension with each
other.11 In these terms, ontological formations are themselves
understood as patterns of practice and meaning constituted at
J. F. Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, Manchester, Manchester University Press, 1986, p. 3.
See also D. Harvey, The Condition of Postmodernity, Cambridge, Basil Blackwell, 1989.
9 F. Jameson, Postmodernism, or, the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism, London, Verso, 1991.
Jameson begins by saying that he is describing postmodernism as a ‘cultural dominant’ (p.
4) and his approach might be described as one of ‘periodisation in dominance’, but within a
few pages he begins to describe the ‘death of the world of appearances’ (p. 9), where ‘depth
is replaced by surface’ (p. 12), and we see the ‘disappearance of the individual subject’, and
the ‘well-nigh universal practice today of what might be called pastiche’ (p. 16).
10 Beck, Risk Society; Z. Bauman, Liquid Modernity, Cambridge, Polity Press, 2000.
11 The two different metaphors — ‘levels’ or ‘assemblages’ — used here work equally well,
though there is a contemporary fetishism for the concept of ‘assemblages’, as if the ‘levels’
metaphor were too mechanical.
8
60
Paul James
different dominant levels of abstraction.12 These formations are
always in tension with each other — sometimes creatively, often
destructively. This alternative approach of engaged theory — a
‘levels approach’ — is neither epochal modernist nor poststructuralist, but it will have particular consequences for understanding
what Taylor calls the ‘immanent frame’. Taylor defines this
contemporary framing of social life as a naturalised order of things
that arose over the last century or so, imbued with the key value of
instrumental rationality. In the terms presented here, the immanent
frame becomes a way of describing one set of responses to a dominant modern matrix of orientations (complicated by emergent
postmodern orientations), rather than the frame understood as a
stand-alone formation of secularity.
Secondly, the levels approach seeks to understand the social
basis of religion and secularism. The approach, as developed here,
treats both faith in the transcendental and ‘opposing’ arguments
that God does not exist as social belief systems, each originating
from different dominant ontological valences, emerging at different
times in human history, but carrying forward to the present. It
seeks to understand (rather than definitively explain) their
animating core in terms of different ways of responding to cultural
and ontological contradictions as part of the human condition. In
this sense, the levels approach is very aware of its own limitations.
For example, it provides a way of understanding the social image
and meaning of ‘God’, but it makes no claims to understand the
transcendental being of God or gods. That is where social theory
stops and theology begins. Social theory can elaborate an answer to
the question, ‘Why do we understand God(s) as we do in our time?’
But it remains completely silent in relation to questions such as
‘Who is God?’ The only thing that might be said here is that modern
theology would do well to be less certain about this question as
well. It is indicative of the unreflexively fashion-framed nature of
modern theology and its parade of culture-dependent answers that
each new theology requires an adjective in front of it: process
theology, God-is-dead theology, liberation theology, eco-theology
and so on.13
12 For an early development of the ‘levels’ approach, see G. Sharp, ‘Constitutive Abstraction
and Social Practice’, Arena, no. 70, 1985, pp. 48–82. For recent expressions, see Geoff Sharp
and John Hinkson’s chapters in the present volume.
13 B. Barber, Beginning at the Beginning, or Why Is It Like This?, Melbourne, Presbytery of Port
Phillip East, 2012, p. 30.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
61
Thirdly, the levels approach has consequences for a related
question: how are we to live in our time? What is the basis of good
human flourishing, living through our relation to others and to
nature? Here this essay travels in the same direction as Ian Barns’
contribution to this volume when he advocates renewed forms of
embodied public conversation about the fundamental nature of the
good life through which the question of the deeper sources of
human flourishing can be re-articulated.14 Our difference here is
that Barns, in common with Stephen Ames and Gordon Preece,
argues for a theologically grounded answer to the basic question of
what constitutes positive human flourishing. By comparison with
this theological position, and in common with John Hinkson and
Geoff Sharp, I argue for a social relational answer. Ames also
describes his approach to human flourishing as relational, but the
difference here is that he grounds his account of human well-being
in communion with God. The constitutive levels approach grounds
the relationality between persons and others — other humans and
others that are other-than-human (of which God, gods, or other
senses of transcendental being and ultimate truth may or may not be
relevant: that is a question for the faith of the persons concerned).
To put the point more analytically, the positive argument here is
that human flourishing depends upon fundamentally reassessing
the current dominant patterns of social relationships between
persons and others (other people, other things and other natures)
as we live across the contradictions of different ontological forms of
practice and meaning. It requires a struggle against the dominant
tendency of our time for more abstract relations to colonise,
instrumentalise, romanticise and reconstitute more embodied
relations of presence and engagement.
In summary, then, the response of the constitutive levels
argument to this third task is that a relational politics of positive
social change and human flourishing will require us (humans) to
negotiate a reflexive ethics of care concerning our relations with
others and our embeddedness within nature. One of the key points
of negotiation here concerns the dialectic between needs and limits.
Currently we are obsessed with both immanent and transcendental
desires, all expressed as ‘needs’. Needs tend to be either defined as
wants or treated as minimal codified rights. Human-rights regimes
or environmental-protection agreements can only be the surface of
14 See I. Barns, ‘Re-imagining a Good Society After Neoliberalism’, in the present volume.
62
Paul James
this process, and sometimes such regimes serve to mask what
actually needs to be done. In parallel, claims that we need to move
to a more post-material or transcendental expression of needs can
be part of the problem — here Hinkson’s contribution to this
volume is seminal. Capitalism and techno-science offer us a secular
and ultimately destructive transcendence that serves to carry social
relations into a post-human world of ‘liberation’ from the
‘constraints’ of our feeble bodies.15
Human flourishing of the kind being argued for here will require
re-embedding and substantially qualifying the hubris of the modern
within a holistic matrix of ontologically different and often
contradictory ways of relating. This essay will suggest that we need
to reinvigorate forms of relations that arose out of analogical and
genealogical ways of being present in customary ways of life
(though not necessarily the cultural content of the ways in which
those relations were once lived). These terms will be defined later.
Specifically, this points to the reclamation of relations of mutuality,
reciprocity, continuity and embeddedness in social life and in
nature. It requires a politics of ontological limits. Elaborating that
argument comprehensively and defining its terms is too massive to
be the focus of a single essay, so we will first come at it tentatively
and side on, through a critique of modern epochalism related to a
focus on the changing nature of religion.
Linking the three themes together, the orienting opening to this
essay argues that epochalism as currently expressed, and however
qualified, is part of an epistemological dominant — a modern way
of knowing — that relates intimately to the contemporary
dominant hubris about what it means to be human. For all of the
new liberal modern sensitivity to ethnocentrism, arrogance and
egotism, proponents of this way of knowing feel in their bones that
‘the modern’ has provided, and will continue to provide, a way of
progressing beyond the limits of other ways of life.16 Its true
believers believe so implicitly in progress, development, growth
and breaking the shackles of the past to allow movement into
15 Here Graham Ward’s superb critique of capitalist materialism (The Politics of Discipleship:
Becoming Postmaterial Citizens, Grand Rapids, Baker Publishing, 2009) would benefit from the
recognition that post-materialism does not actually offer us a way out of the present crises
— postmodern capitalism in intersection with techno-science now offers us a post-material
transcendence that threatens to fragment the foundations of what it has meant to be human.
16 Some go further in a poststructuralist vein, usually overlaying a modern confidence about
change, to project a postmodern liberation from life as we now know it or have known it —
the post-human world of cyborgs and signs.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
63
future ‘freedoms’ and ‘happiness’ that they would never think of
what they do as a kind of proselytising.
The problem with this is much more than a theoretical or even an
ideological one. It is intensely practical. Modern globalising ways
of life have a profound tendency to colonise, reframe and distort all
other ways of being in the name of this progress. Other ways of life
that do not come quickly and compliantly to the modern dialogical
table tend to be reduced ideologically to past anachronisms,
romantic others, irrelevant bystanders, marginalised threats or
terrorists. Future possibilities and grand imaginaries are defended.
All the while the world is brought to the brink of nuclear warfare
or irrevocable climate chaos.
It is not that being modern is bad in itself. Modern ways of
being and knowing offer subtle and powerful possibilities.
Secondly, it is not that the modern can ever be something in itself.
In our time, and in the times of others, modern ways of being and
doing are always in intersection with ontologically different ways
of being and doing. Colonising life-worlds, whether through soft
consumption systems or hard war machines, tends to be done by
ordinary people, themselves formed in the intersection of different
ontological conditions (ordinary, complex and contradictory
people). Sets of contending values come together to explain and
legitimise an invasion, an intervention or a quiet take-over, and
there is no central ideological contender that rules them all.
Instrumental rationality, the orienting value that Charles Taylor
and Jürgen Habermas single out for critique, could never stand
up by itself if it were the only ideological strut in the modern
frame.
Therefore, it is not just dialogue through interpretative
rationality that we need. Recent high-profile serial offenders in this
system of ontological imperialism include George W. Bush, Tony
Blair, Nicolas Sarkozy, Vladimir Putin and Barack Obama. They are
all syncretic blunderers rather than single-minded rationalists. The
War on Islamic Otherness that two of them initiated, and a third
continued under another name, was far from being framed by
instrumental rationality. Why would clear-headed instrumental
rationalists waste so many lives and burn so much money on a
small group of criminals? As decision makers, Bush, Blair,
Berlusconi and Co. were witless modernists who, at the same time
as conducting (tragic) wars of global defence in the name of
modern ideologies of rational order, homeland purity, market
Paul James
64
freedom and the ‘Common Word’,17 also reached back to, and distorted, Christian truths. These truths, such as the ‘Will of God’, are
traditional in their epistemological form even as the propaganda
machines were modern/postmodern. Tony Blair very deeply believes
in the Roman Catholic God, but at the same time he did not formally
seek acceptance into the Catholic Church while he was prime minister because he also believes in modern secular politics. Being a
Catholic in multicultural Britain is not the best way to power.
* * *
The essay begins with a preliminary foray into the question of
periodising, and then goes on to develop a definition of changing
forms of religion that connects to an understanding of changing
dominant ontological formations. Before taking these next steps,
my colleagues have asked me to name my place in this process —
to be personal. Why do I appear to be so critical of Charles Taylor?
What is my response to the secular age that he theorises? And
where do I stand in relation to the religion that he implicitly
espouses as bringing intensified focused meaning back to a world
that is swirling with often empty, consumer-oriented choices over
meaning? I am critical of Taylor’s A Secular Age because it promises
so much but unfolds into a messy approach that countermands its
own intentions. For me, our time, given the current manifold
cultural, economic, ecological and political crises that threaten the
very existence of humans on this planet, demands a more comprehensive theorising. It requires a theoretical politics that firstly
offers (even implicitly) a stronger practical-theoretical alternative to
the poetry of faith with which Taylor concludes.18 Even good poetry
and reflexive faith are not enough. Geoff Sharp develops this point
with considerable force. Secondly, it requires an epistemology that
qualifies its own certainties, truths and dogmas without descending into postmodern relativism. Thirdly, and most importantly, it
requires that we reconstruct the relation between different ontological formations, including the relationship between different
17 ‘Common Word’ refers to an interfaith dialogue that Tony Blair’s Faith Foundation
supported ‘to bring Muslims and Christians together to find a common basis of cooperation
and mutual respect through scripture’ (C. Hitchens and T. Blair, Be it Resolved Religion Is a
Force for Good: The Debate of Our Time, Sydney, Allen & Unwin, 2011, p. 44). It involves an
ecumenical emptying out of the differences between the faiths by finding bits of text that
have similar inflections.
18 The concept of a ‘poetry of faith’ is mine rather than Taylor’s, but it is intended to
encapsulate the way in which he and others use a belief in their God to stand in for a
recognition of the ineffable.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
65
ways of knowing and believing, such that more grounded valences
of social life (embedding our relations to other and to nature) are
brought back into balance with our current capacities to construct
and deconstruct the world in which we all live. The essay as it
unfolds will elaborate each of these standpoints.
What Does It Mean to Ask ‘What Does It Mean That We
Live in a Secular Age?’?
Underlying the classically modern analytic mode of enquiry was
(and sometimes still is) a desire to understand the social whole. In
particular, theorists wanted to understand this or that social whole
as occurring in a distinctive time in the history of the human
condition. It remains an important, if vexed, task. Theorising the
social whole without reducing it to an epochal singularity, for a
brief moment the holy grail of social theory, unfortunately came to
be relegated to one of the display cabinets of the theory museum.
The theorists associated with that search were important, but they
were never central enough to generate a lineage of theory or even
to find connections between each other. They ranged from
Raymond Williams and Pierre Bourdieu to Michael Mann and
Maurice Godelier. However, intellectual passions changed and, in
the years of the late-twentieth century and into the present, social
enquiry largely gave up on that question.
Enquiry has tended to bifurcate along two dominant lineages.
Along one lineage, poststructuralism, particularly its postmodern
variant, increasingly made it a sin to characterise the social whole.
Michel Foucault, for example, could write a brilliant account of the
metamorphosis of punishment from the traditional to the modern
— and indeed quite happily use the term ‘modern society’ — while
studiously avoiding making any claims to a social whole. Along
another lineage, social enquiry saw a revival of the fortunes of
empiricism. Empirical generalisation as the ground of modern
analytical enquiry had never gone away. But now its (fetishised)
ideological dominance meant that legitimate enquiry could only
make generalised claims about specific fields, regions, themes or
instances.19
19 There is a beautiful irony in this retreat from generalising theory that is worth noting. At the
same time that generalising theory lost its hold, a generalising category of social relations
gripped the imaginations of both academic analysts and journalistic commentators — this,
of course, was the category of ‘the global’. In this emerging imaginary, globalisation was
66
Paul James
In this context, what does it mean to ask about the meaning of
living in a secular age? Both Taylor’s and Lyotard’s responses to the
question of periodising throw up complementary problems. This is
despite their apparently antithetical standpoints. Lyotard writes:
From this point of view, we can see that historical periodisation belongs to an obsession that is characteristic of
modernity. Periodisation is a way of placing events in diachrony,
and diachrony is ruled by the principle of revolution. In the
same way that modernity contains the promise of its overcoming, it is obliged to mark, to date, the end of one period
and the beginning of the next. Since one is inaugurating an
age reputed to the entirely new, it is right to set the clock to the
new time, and to start it from zero again. In Christianity,
Cartesianism or Jacobinism, this same gesture designated a
Year One, that of revelation and redemption in one case, of
birth and renewal in the second, or again of revolution and
reappropriation of liberties.20
It is an apparently elegant reprise: the modern has to epochalise
itself, hence we develop concepts such as the Anthropocene. It even
has to mark its own end with a prefixed concept that is selfcontaining of the period it surpasses — the postmodern. However,
there are deeper problems with this approach. Historical
periodisation is certainly an obsession within the modern
(constructivist) sense of time, and Lyotard is right to both
historicise it and to criticise the way in which it fetishises new
beginnings. However, Lyotard succumbs to his own critique of the
modern tendency to flatten difference. In particular, he comfortably
flattens out the difference between Christianity, Cartesianism and
Jacobinism, as if they have the same ontological foundations
simply because they can be found coterminously in human history.
Even if Christianity, at one level, now works with modern time, the
ontological basis of its entire belief system is cosmological rather
understood as a process of social interconnection, a process that was in different ways
connecting people across planet Earth. Globalisation as a practice and subjectivity
connecting the (global) social whole thus became the standout object of critical enquiry. In
other words, globalisation demanded generalising attention at the very moment that
residual ideas that an all-embracing theory might be found to explain such a phenomenon
were effectively dashed. This has profound consequences for the nature of globalisation
theory and how we might understand different approaches. However, that is another story
and cannot be pursued here. See M. B. Steger and P. James, ‘Three Dimensions of Subjective
Globalization’, ProtoSociology, vol. 27, 2011, pp. 53–70, from which the present section of the
essay draws its argument.
20 J. F. Lyotard, The Inhuman: Reflections on Time, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1991, pp. 25–6.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
67
than modern. Christ is the realised eschatology of an embracing
universal time in which God is atemporal, the maker of time. By
profound contrast, and for all their traditional roots, the Jacobin
notion of Year Zero was part of a modern attempt to decimalise
time — with ten hours in the day and ten days in the week — to get
rid of all Christian and pagan references within the temporal
system.
In contrast to this move by Lyotard, Taylor is usually careful to
distinguish the stages or phases of Christianity. The big shift in his
terms is from what he accurately characterises as reorientation in
the focus of the dominant social imaginary from ‘the cosmos’ — in
his terms a pre-modern understanding of the moral metaphysical
order — to ‘the universe’ of abstracted laws and secular time. He
reminds us that even the term ‘secular’ comes from saeculum,
meaning century or age.21 However, the unintended flatness of his
methodological approach catches him up, and we find later that
instead of maintaining some consistency with his narrative of a
cosmos-to-universe transformation he begins talking about the
‘modern cosmic imaginary’ (emphasis added).22 Again, to draw
upon the approach that will be elaborated later in this essay, using
such a phrase requires a theory of ontological contradiction. Can
something be cosmic — in the sense that it is framed by a
traditional cosmology — and modern at the same time? Yes, it can,
but not in the terms that Taylor gives us. Expressed in these
alternative terms of ‘levels in contradiction’, Catholicism today is a
globalising modern institution that draws upon modern organisational techniques and structures at the same time that its belief
system is traditional cosmological and its marketing arm is
postmodern. The Vatican is a body/machine that like all contemporary corpor/ations takes capitalist profit, while at the same time
its executive takes communion by eating the body of Christ.
Understanding how a religious organisation can be so structured
— let alone the world so cleaved — requires an approach that can
handle formations in tension and contradiction, related to the
unevenness of various modes of practice.
A related problem for Taylor concerns how he defines the time of
the universe as the time of ‘secular time’. There are a lot of ‘times’
in that sentence, but each of their uses points to a problem of
21 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 54.
22 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 351.
Paul James
68
explanation. In other words, the very thing that Taylor is trying to
explain — ‘the secular’ — becomes the name of the form of
temporality in which a temporally specific phenomenon arises that
frames how people live: ‘People who are in the saeculum are
embedded in ordinary time, they are living the life of ordinary
time: as against those who have turned away from this in order to
live closer to eternity’.23 ‘There is a risk here’, he says, ‘because I’m
already using the word “secular” (and in three senses, already!) for
features of our age’.24 And indeed there is. However, this stain on
Taylor’s methodology is quickly passed over by him as he rushes
on to make a new narrative connection.
Defining Religion
As a way of exemplifying the methodological problems with
Charles Taylor’s approach and beginning to describe an alternative
approach developed by the Arena editors and others, the next
section after this one moves to define the ontological formations
that have been implied in the discussion thus far: customary
tribalism, traditionalism, modernism and postmodernism. But first
there is the issue of how we should define religion. Taylor adroitly
declines to do so. His gentle refusal takes a similar series of steps to
those taken in his recognition that he uses ‘the secular’ in a number
of competing ways: first, we get a disarming admission that there
might be a problem; second, we read a couple of intriguing
methodological allusions; and third, we move on, allowing the
inconsistencies to be clothed in an aura of narrative elegance where
methodological inconsistencies become the source of interpretative
insight.
There is no doubt that Taylor’s writing is brimming with brilliant
interpretative insights. He is right, for example, to bring in the key
concept of ‘transcendence’ as central to a possible definition. He
begins by recognising, very importantly, that the usual definition
tends to be reductive:
But if we are prudent (or perhaps cowardly) and reflect that
we are trying to understand a set of forms and changes which
have arisen in one particular civilisation, that of the modern
West — or in an earlier incarnation, Latin Christendom — we
23 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 55.
24 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 54.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
69
see to our relief that we don’t need to forge a definition which
covers everything ‘religious’ in all human societies for all
ages.25
He refuses to overgeneralise the concept of religion and wants to
emphasise how it is located historically. But then we do not get a
definition at all, not even for the modern West. This would appear
to be a reasonable move — except that, firstly, 400 pages later he
ends up drawing heavily on someone else’s generalising definition.
This becomes theorising by expediency.
Secondly, there is the issue that treating Western ‘late modernity’
as a temporal-geographical region that can be examined in itself is
astoundingly naive. Charles Taylor may not have read Jack
Goody’s The East in the West and similar volumes when they began
to be published nearly two decades ago, but it is now generally
recognised that processes of globalisation, imperial extension,
regional interdependence and local change, at least from the time of
Latin Christendom, mean that Europe has long been part of shifting
global and postcolonial interrelations.26
Thirdly, there is the sticking point that the whole narrative
framework of A Secular Age needs a general definition to make
possible the epochal claim that religion (not just Christianity)
becomes a choice across Western ‘late modernity’, while the
imminent frame becomes the predominant setting for that choice,
including the choice to be secular. The definition that Taylor
appears to accept in general is as follows:
Religion for us consists of actions, beliefs and institutions
predicated upon the assumption of the existence of either
supernatural entities with powers of agency, or impersonal
powers or processes possessed of moral purpose which have
the capacity to set the conditions of, or to intervene in, human
affairs.27
What this definition is trying to do implicitly is handle differences
in religious practice and meaning. It puts its emphasis on unnamed
supernatural entities or powers with moral purpose — in other
25 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 15.
26 J. Goody, The East in the West, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1996.
27 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 429, citing Roy Wallis and Steve Bruce. Taylor compounds the
problem when he also favourably cites David Martin’s definition that, in effect, requires
(modern) science as the counter-force to religion: ‘By “religion” I mean the acceptance of
reality beyond the observable world known to science, to which are ascribed meanings and
purposes completing and transcending those of the purely human realm’, cited on p. 818.
70
Paul James
words, the other-than-human. The connection to the social is
rightly built around the acknowledgment that it is predicated on an
‘assumption’ of the existence of something beyond the human.
However, the definition has problems that Taylor himself hints at.
It cannot, for example, encompass a wonderfully contradictory
religion such as Buddhism, which, in its classical post-traditional
form (or, to be more accurate, its modern-framed neo-traditional
form), assumes no supernatural entities or powers with moral
purpose. The definition also has difficulties in helping us to
understand customary or tribal religions28 where conceptions of
‘purpose’ are not self-evidently ‘moral’.
Arguably, a better way of setting up the definition involves
putting the emphasis on the nature of the practices and meanings
of religion. That is, a different and perhaps better starting point for
defining religion is to emphasise the relations of religiosity rather
than the objects of worship or dedication. Thus, in terms of the
levels argument being developed here, religion is defined as a
relatively bounded system of beliefs, symbols and practices that addresses
the nature of existence through communion with others and Otherness,
lived as both taking in and spiritually transcending socially grounded
ontologies of time, space, embodiment and knowing.29
This alternative definition is intended, for example, to avoid the
usual dichotomous understandings of supernatural and natural
beings, or the split between sacredness and secularity. It takes into
account the issue that the modernist dualism of immanence and
transcendence is a socially framed dualism that would make no
sense to a customary elder or tribal sorcerer, and limited sense to a
traditional shaman, pujari, cleric or lama. And it also takes into
account John Hinkson’s argument (see his essay in this volume)
that there are also many forms of secular transcendence. The
question of how different religions (or other regimes and discursive
groupings) handle the relation between immanence and transcendence is, in other words, ontologically context dependent.
Moreover, by using the term ‘relatively bounded system’ it curtails
the sense that any old personal or momentary expression of spir-
28 This point refers to those tribal religions that have not been thoroughly traditionalised
through encounters with Christianity or other processes.
29 This definition comes from work that I did with Peter Mandaville: P. James and P.
Mandaville (eds), Globalization and Culture, Vol. 2: Globalizing Religions, London, Sage
Publications, 2010, and published as ‘Globalizing Religions: World Without End, or the End
of Religion’ in Arena Journal, no. 39–40, 2012/2013, pp. 229–52.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
71
ituality constitutes a religion. By the same phrase, the definition
makes no claims about the distinction in any particular social
setting between a religious and non-religious practice, or between
one religion and another. In its creed, Buddhism has no gods, but
in practice in India and Japan, Buddhist temples are full of syncretic
spiritual icons and animist gods. These are similarly contextdependent questions. Thus, without going down the path of Peter
Beyer’s version of systems theory, it allows for a full recognition of
his argument that the process of differentiating religious expressions/communities as distinct religions was in practice and theory
a modern and modernising process.30
The definition also points to the issue that many contemporary
religious communities have a contradictory relation to basic
ontologies such as time, space and embodiment. One dimension
that distinguishes traditional religions from conventional conceptions of political community is that traditional religious communities
are not generally premised upon, or limited to, a particular
territorial space. For traditional religions, transversality has been
part and parcel of the formation of their sense of spatiality. We see
this, for example, in the context of the Jewish diaspora, a chosen
people dispersed across the face of the earth. In the emerging
dominance of modern sensibilities, the traditional conception of
Zion, once a transcendental claim to being close to God wherever
one was, became a desperate modern search for an abstract
territory to call home. Almost any territory would have worked for
the purpose of modern political Zionism. But one worked better
that the rest. ‘Israel’ became the place to settle by a mixture of
imperial subterfuge and the possibilities it offered for being the
transcendental traditional Zion and, at the same time, being an
immanent modern home that could be legitimised by completely
rewriting the ancient history of the tribes of Israel in terms of the
Chosen People of that land. Abraham from Ur of the Chaldees
became a Jew, and Israel became at once cosmologically eternal and
part of modern, ‘continuous’, rewritten, self-legitimising history. It
is true that this passage has been written to emphasise the clash of
ontologies, but you get my point.
30 P. Beyer, ‘The Religious System of Global Society’, Numen, vol. 45, no. 1, 1998, pp. 1–29.
72
Paul James
Defining Different Ontological Formations, and thus
Different Dominant Forms of Religion across Changing
World-Time
All the preceding discussion is pushing towards a single claim: that
understanding religion (and secularity) is best served by analytically
distinguishing different ontologies of practice and meaning,
including examining the lived contradictions that pertain when in
practice people live across those ontologically different ‘levels’. The
designation of levels is analytical and provisional, with all the
weight of those words taken seriously.
The words in the definition of religion presented above —
transcending socially grounded ontologies of time, space, embodiment and
knowing — point to the next steps in setting up the counterapproach. That is, just as a full definition of such complex
phenomena needs be ontologically grounded, rather than just
based on either the phenomenal experiences of religious believers
or the doctrines of their religious philosophers, so, too, when it
comes to defining formations such as modernity or postmodernity.
When they are understood in phenomenal or factorial terms there
is, arguably, no solid basis upon which to build the historically
specific understanding of their many variations. The variations
turn into Hindu elephants with badly explained or weird body
parts. In the case of the modern elephant, its eyes flash with constant
self-reflexivity, its legs always run fast, it has a body like a serpent
that twists and turns, and its trunk reaches out to accommodate all
the qualifications. One can only marvel at how a liquid modern
elephant might act. Responding to this problem, different gatherings of writers — the ‘multiple modernities’, ‘another modernity’
and ‘second modernity’ advocates — complicate things further.31
They decide that one elephant is not enough, and set a whole herd
of them running across the global landscape, trampling everything
before it into the category of the ‘premodern’.
It is worth taking a moment to reflect upon why it has become so
hard to find an actual, let alone good, definition of modernity or the
modern, or of postmodernity or the postmodern condition. Apart
31 See S. N. Eisenstadt, ‘Multiple Modernities’, Daedalus, vol. 129, no. 1, 2000, pp. 1–29. This
seminal and sophisticated text, later taken up by many others, rightly sets out to counter a
tendency in the literature to conflate modernisation and Westernisation. The problem is that,
for all its sophistication, it defines modernity in reductive Weberian terms that presume its
own outcome. See also S. Lash, Another Modernity: A Different Rationality, Oxford, Blackwell
Publishers, 1999.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
73
from a short period of intense focus at the end of the twentieth
century, most writings defer the process of definition in favour or
evocation of this or that characteristic of the phenomena. Perhaps
this gives us a clue to part of the problem of explanation and the
issue of projecting an alternative politics. Fredric Jameson and
David Harvey, for example, have written challenging book-length
evocations of the phenomena, but those books contain no direct or
ontologically grounded definitions. A bevy of other relevant books
define the terms loosely and phenomenally — for example, sometimes the modern is equated to increased speed and expansion,
begging questions about how fast or extended social life has to be
to be modern. And sometimes writers defer the task with sophisticated self-consciousness. Anthony Giddens, for example, begins:
‘As a first approximation, let us simply say the following:
“modernity” refers to modes of social life or organization which
emerged in Europe from about the seventeenth century onwards’.
And then he immediately acknowledges the limits of his nondefinition. All this passage does, in his words, is associate ‘modernity
with a time period, a particular mode of practice [organisation] and
with an initial geographical location [Europe], but for the moment
leaves its major characteristics locked away in a black box’.32 The
Eurocentrism of this is not dissimilar to that presented by Charles
Taylor — both writers know that they are being Europe focused,
but they can do little about it.
Taylor’s exposition slowly opens up the black box, as does
Giddens’s analysis. They are both too good as scholars to do
otherwise. However, like Giddens, Taylor gives us not a definition
but a list of associated forces. The modern social imaginary, Taylor
suggests, has been built upon three dynamics: the lifting out of the
economy as a distinct domain or objectified reality; the simultaneous
emergence of the public sphere as the place of increasingly mediated
interchange counter-posed to the intimate or private sphere; and the
recognition of the sovereignty of the people, treated as a new collective agency even as it is made up of individuals who seek selfaffirmation in the other spheres.33 These are three historical developments, among others, that are relevant to what we have been
calling a modern ontological formation. But they are just important
32 A. Giddens, The Consequences of Modernity, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1990. His institutional
dimensions of modernity are enhanced surveillance capacities, control of the means of
violence, capitalism and industrialism.
33 C. Taylor, Modern Social Imaginaries, Durham, Duke University Press, 2004.
74
Paul James
historical factors. They do not help us to ground the nature of the
modern, nor do they explain, either singularly or synthetically, the
changing nature of religion across the changing dominance of
different formations from the traditional to the modern.
The most direct definition of the classical discussions is Lyotard’s.
‘I will use the term modern’, he says, ‘to designate any science that
legitimates itself with reference to a metadiscourse of this kind
making an explicit appeal to some grand narrative’.34 Hence, he says,
‘I define the postmodern as incredulity towards metanarratives’.35
One of the many problems with this interconnected definition of the
modern/postmodern is that other means of enquiry, including
traditional science (otherwise known as the ‘pre-modern’ sciences;
sometimes called magic, alchemy or sorcery), also appeal to metanarratives about the nature of things. In terms of the engaged theory
presented here, they are ontologically different kinds of metanarratives, with the traditional sciences drawn together as cosmologies
and the modern sciences drawn together as universalities.
Another problem with Lyotard’s definitions is that they limit the
defining of a complex formation to a single ontological category:
namely, knowing (or to be more precise, the grounds of knowledge
— epistemology). Admittedly, the present approach only works
with five such categories — temporality, spatiality, corporeality,
epistemology and performativity — and many more could be
chosen.36 But at least in the present approach this is done though a
reflexive analytical claim that the number of chosen categories is
contingently determined, firstly, in consideration of the fact that
they are ontologically foundational, and secondly through the
usefulness test. Does the number and combination of the categories
chosen provide a sufficient sense of the complexity of the human
condition without becoming too unwieldy and heavy? More
importantly, is this done in relation to an argument that these
categories are basic to being human?
34 Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, p. xxiii.
35 Lyotard, The Postmodern Condition, p. xxiv.
36 In Globalism, Nationalism, Tribalism (London, Sage Publications, 2006) and related writings
prior to that time, I used the categorical list of temporality, spatiality, corporeality and
epistemology as sufficient for the task at hand. If performativity were added to the list then
it would need to be seen quite differently from how some postmodern theorists use it. Judith
Butler, for example, says that ‘Gender reality is performative which means, quite simply, that
it is real only to the extent that it is performed’ (cited in J. Loxley, Performativity, Abingdon,
Routledge, 2007, p. 118). By contrast, the present approach does not treat a single ontological
category as so foundationally in itself as to make it the basis of an analysis, nor does it treat
its relationship to the ‘real’ as singular.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
75
A few other things need to be said before the alternative definitions are laid out. Ontological formations are not treated as ideal
types, but neither are they ever understood as standalone
formations, at least not in post-tribal history. They are formationsin-dominance, co-existent and co-temporal. Secondly, the names
for these formations — the customary, the traditional, the modern
and the postmodern — are old conventional names used in various
ways that are now sometimes uncomfortable or awkward. However, rather than inventing neologisms, the approach works with
given names and seeks to redefine them in terms of their ontological
bases. Thirdly, rather than defining a formation in temporal distinction to other formations — using a term such as ‘pre-modern’ to
designate all that has come before the modern — formations are
defined both comparatively and for themselves. All of this means
that they cannot be treated as four great epochs fading into each
other. It means that we can talk of dialectics of continuity and
discontinuity across our time on this planet. Fourthly, it means that
in order to distinguish between different formations we need a notion
of valences or orientations — ways in which different categories of
being are lived. (This last point will be elaborated in a moment.)
These moves can be compared to how Charles Taylor both uses
terms such as ‘modernity’ and ‘pre-modernity’, and calls his social
forms ‘ideal types’ where they are defined in terms of phenomenal
characteristics, though he hints at customary relations (and given
that he lives in Canada it is hard to see how customary relations
could be so buried in this particular analysis). His first ideal type is
the ancien régime type, in his words based on ‘pre-modern’ ideas of
order during a time when the world was enchanted. We had
porous selves, and our relations were grouped around constituent
orders: nobility, peasants and so on. It ended around the turn of the
nineteenth century but has an unspecified beginning. The second is
the mobilisation type, the basis of the ‘Age of Mobilisation’, which
ended around ‘1950 (perhaps more exactly 1960)’.37 In terms of the
millennia of world history, it is hard to be more stupidly exact.
And the third is the authenticity type, the basis of the ‘Age of
Authenticity’ from the 1960s to the present. It is characterised by
expressive individualism, consumerism and a buffered self who
seeks his or her authentic life based on the right to choose. This
double move — treating social forms as epochs and then as ideal
37 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 471.
76
Paul James
types — means that numerous qualifications have to follow, and
they do — hundreds of them. At the same time, Taylor also makes
some unsustainable epochal claims about beginnings and ends.
The ancien régime has gone. ‘All this has been dismantled and
replaced by something quite different.’38 The porous self has been
‘replaced’ by the buffered self; the older worlds are ‘lost’ to us; and
‘modern social forms exist exclusively in secular time’.39 By the end
of the book, Taylor is forced back to this point and says, in contradiction with himself, that ‘We cannot understand our present
situation by single ideal type’.40 This problem is more than the need
for a good editor.
Overall, the lineages that Taylor traces are fascinating and
compelling, but his method does not serve him well. In particular,
it cannot systematically handle the question of contradiction within
and between his different ideal types. By contrast, defining life
forms in terms of their ontological form — as I want to do here —
is a quite different exercise from setting up ideal types. Each of
these life forms is defined in terms of socially specific modes of time,
space, embodiment, knowledge and performance, intersecting
unevenly across various modes of practice and integration. In other
words, rather than defining these life forms in terms of each other
or beginning with the modern as the starting point or master epoch
— with the past relegated wanly to a singular ‘pre-modern’ and the
future projected as an end-of-the-modern ‘postmodern’ — the
levels method defines each of these life forms in terms of their
orientation to a common set of categories. These are categories
lived in foundationally different ways across different settings of
the human condition. In this kind of engaged theory, when such
ontological categories come together as patterned, sustained
relations, they are provisionally called ontological formations.41 When,
in a particular time and place, an ontological formation becomes a
social dominant, then that time and place can provisionally be
characterised in terms of such a dominant. Connected to these two
points, what I hope to show is how this method handles something
that Taylor’s method cannot — issues of social and ontological
contradiction, both creative and destructive (see Table 1).
38
39
40
41
Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 61.
Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 207.
Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 514.
For an elaboration of the definitions that follow in relation to exchange, temporality and
embodiment, see James, Globalism, Nationalism, Tribalism, chapters 6, 7 and 8 respectively.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
77
Table 1. Levels of the Social in Relation to Levels of Analysis
The Customary as an Ontological Formation
The customary is defined by the way that analogical, genealogical
and mythological valences come to constitute different social
practices — production, exchange, enquiry, communication, organisation and enquiry — in relation to basic categories of existence:
time, space, embodiment, performance and knowledge.42 The three
defining valences have been chosen because they arguably give a
minimal sense of the complexity of customary (including tribal)
formations. They have overlapping consequences, but they can be
analytically distinguished. An orientation to an analogical valence
has its primary embedding in the relation between the natural and
the social, or what is called the ‘nature-culture’ contradiction; a
genealogical valence is primarily embodied in the relation between
42 Here the term ‘valence’ comes from the Latin valentia, meaning strength or capacity. It comes
via chemistry, where from the nineteenth century it has been used to refer to the ‘combining
power of an element’. More recently it has been used in psychology to express an orientation.
78
Paul James
birth, becoming and mortality; and a mythological valence is
primarily expressed in the relation between practice and meaning.
Speaking broadly, these valences are treated as foundational for the
human condition, even today. Configured tightly together as social
dominants, they are the basis for an ontological formation,
provisionally called ‘the customary’. A customary tribal religion in
these terms tells stories and practises mythologies about the
intimate natural-social realm. The subjects of those mythologies are
genealogies (relations of mutuality) in animated social nature. They
are narratives bringing forth ever-present origins, ongoing
reciprocal connections and deep continuities.
Within a constitutive frame understood in terms of the primacy
of such valences, time, for example, moves analogically with nature,
linked to diurnal patterns, seasons and years, but is also embodied
in life stages and lifetimes through genealogical rituals and cycles.
Time, like space, is nature-culture. It is expressed in mythological
sequences, severally connecting past and present, though without
those connections expressing something singular beyond
themselves. In such a setting, the immanent and transcendental are
not phenomenally distinguishable, though at times of intensified
meaning and during rites of passage a sense of the sacred is lifted
into relief. In other words, this approach allows us to make sense of
how customary time is ontologically different from traditional,
modern and postmodern time, as discussed later. And as an aside
it should be said that this kind of approach to the ontological
meaning of time — changing across different dominant ontological
formations — provides a way of avoiding Charles Taylor’s and
Gordon Preece’s tendency to reduce the discussion to two kinds of
time: Messianic (read: Christian) time and empty modern time.
The different valences outlined here (and the further valences
elaborated in relation to traditional, modern and postmodern ways
of life, described later) are rarely in a simple one-to-one relation to
each other. It is possible under certain pressures and at certain
times, for example, for mythological relations to be disembedded
from analogical and genealogical relations. Similarly, it is possible
for customary relations to be in dominance even though certain
modes of practice in that setting have been traditionalised or
modernised. The most obvious example here is the way in which a
mode of production framed by customary relations can largely be
supplanted while other modes of practice remain firmly in place.
Nevertheless, none of these relations, by themselves, make a way of
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
79
life customary or tribal. Without being continually re-embedded in
a relatively complex matrix of customary relations, analogical and
genealogical meanings and practices can gradually be emptied out.
It is not just the (modern) immanent frame that has the potential to
empty out meaning in this world. The (traditional) transcendental
claims of Pentecostal evangelists claiming a direct experience to a
universalising God can be just as destructive in relation to their
customary brethren as modernising colonialists. It continues to be
their mission on earth, self-consciously and proudly proclaimed.
And it is a well-intentioned form of ontological genocide: the systematic and intended destruction of another way of life.
This genocide is now put in much more subtle ways than under
the Catholic conquistadors, or even the more gentile London
Missionary Society. For example, Ethnos360 — formed in 1942 as
New Tribes Mission — currently has more than 3000 representatives across the world, with the aim of ‘reaching people who have
no access to the Gospel’. This would be a fine mission if it stayed at
that level, but it does not take much digging to find more comprehensive aims. In a recent Mission News, under the subheading
‘From Animism to Truth’, the authors ask us to pray with them for
the end of a certain cultural understanding: ‘As the Kendawangan
people learn of the truth through the amazing stories in the Bible,
pray they abandon their animistic beliefs and that they will have
receptive hearts’.43 ‘This is a spiritual battle’, writes another missionary, responding to the lack of receptiveness from the Tobo people.44
On the other hand, it is also possible for new forms and meanings to be drawn syncretically back into a customary formation. In
situations dominated by customary relations there was (and is), for
example, no singular Dreamtime — that is, until cosmologically
informed anthropologists such as Baldwin Spencer attributed
modern systematicity to these many mythologies and gave them a
singular name.45 The subjects of his anthropological analysis had
43 Ethnos360, ‘God’s Living Word Comes to the Kendawangan People’, Mission News,
11 May 2014, <http://usa.ntm.org/mission-news/79629/god-s-living-word-comes-to-thekendawangan-people>, accessed 26 June 2017.
44 Ethnos360, ‘The Triumphs and the Challenges’, Mission News, 27 May 2014, <https://
ethnos360.org/mission-news/the-triumphs-and-the-challenges>, accessed 26 June 2017.
45 See M. Charlesworth, Religious Inventions, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1997. In
other words, this is not to suggest that ‘the Dreaming’ is not a lived way of describing
practice and meaning in our time among tribal/traditional/modern Aboriginal people, just
as the terms developed by anthropologists to describe kinship relations — ‘clan’, ‘moiety’,
‘patrilineage’, ‘matrilineage’ and even the concept ‘kinship’ — have been taken on as useful
for describing connections between people under the dominance of a tribal formation.
80
Paul James
told, reworked and retold mythical stories for generations without
an emphasis on a singular whole, evoking the meanings of these
connections rather than arranging them into a singular cosmology.
But, with a new layer of epistemological access to old ways,
perceptions changed. It adds to our argument rather than
contradicts it that subsequently many Aboriginal people came to
live that new abstraction, ‘the Dreaming’. It serves well as an
integrating description of prior beliefs. This was part of a process of
change of a more comprehensive kind from the time of ‘settlement’
all the way into the postcolonial present — the customary being
overlaid by more abstract formations or practice. It had good and
bad consequences.
This begins to hint at an alternative politics. Against the immanent frame, Taylor wants to return to poetic faith. The reflexive
return that I am implicitly advocating here suggests more broadly
that different cultures should explore different ways of bringing
contradictory ontological frames into creative relation with each
other, self-consciously aware that more abstract valences have a
historically proven tendency to subordinate and colonise ‘prior’
forms, and this tendency needs to be challenged.
The history of traditional (often religious) and modern (usually
capitalist) colonisation has been tragic. Through the invocation of
traditional values (often Christian) and modern values (usually
liberal rational), ‘we’ sought to civilise, destroy, bring to faith or
assimilate ‘them’. In response, customary indigenous peoples have
done many things: resist, rebel, go bush, get drunk or lie down and
die.46 They have become middle-class entrepreneurs,47 rejected
capitalism and developed syncretic alternatives. But they have not
simply disappeared. Sometimes, such as in the Dreaming example,
they have responded in creative syncretic ways. More often they
have become troubled. Joel Robbins’s book Becoming Sinners
describes the tormented process of negotiating ontological difference in one community where a customary culture provides the
grounds of human security in gardening and hunting, and another
culture, a Pentecostal Christian one, ‘directs attention away from
46 The reference here is to Richard Trudgen’s inspiring book Why Warriors Lie Down and Die,
Darwin, Aboriginal Resource and Development Services, 2000.
47 The reference here is to Marcia Langton’s 2012 Boyer Lectures, ‘The Quiet Revolution:
Indigenous People and the Resources Boom’, ABC Radio National, 18 November – 2
December, <http://www.abc.net.au/radionational/programs/boyerlectures/series/2012boyer-lectures/4305696>, accessed 26 June 2017.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
81
the earthly landscapes’.48 But cultural negotiation predominates.
Damian Grenfell’s perceptive work describes the complex negotiation of domains in another community where death brings together
three worlds of mourning: the customary (dead ancestors), the traditional (heaven) and the modern (the nation state):
Yes [says one Timorese woman] the spirits can create
problems [for us living persons], because they can ask God —
the ancestors are second and God is first — and so the spirits
can ask ‘Can God open the door for me or not?’ And then if
God opens the door for the spirits they can enter the world
and create problems if the living did not give them [at their
burial] tais [customary woven cloth] or contribute money, and
so this is the way that death causes problems.49
In this process, the tribal understanding of the sacred domain of the
ancestors (lulik) defers to a traditional Catholic cosmology that needs
to be the One and Only, even as it folds that cosmology of being first
back into a new, customary, mythologically framed religion.
The Traditional as an Ontological Formation
The traditional is defined by the way in which analogical, genealogical and mythological valences are drawn into a cosmological and
metaphorical reframing of different social practices — production,
exchange, communication, organisation and enquiry — in relation
to basic categories of existence: time, space, embodiment and knowledge. This, like the previous definition, is a working definition, but
I think that it meets the basic criteria of good method: practical
usefulness, analytical coherence, simple complexity and normative
reflexivity. In societies dominated by traditional ways of life, the
second-order valences of the cosmological and metaphorical
tended (and tend) to be lived in conjunction with each other. It is
only possible philosophically to separate out or define the terms of
these valences of social life, and it is to this end that traditional
philosophers have been devoted for centuries.
In this approach, traditionalism, as I am using the concept, is quite
48 J. Robbins, Becoming Sinners: Christianity and Moral Torment in a Papua New Guinea Society,
Berkeley, University of California Press, 2004, p. 33.
49 D. Grenfell, ‘Remembering the Dead from the Customary to the Modern in Timor-Leste’,
Local-Global, vol. 11, 2012, pp. 86–108, cited from p. 92. See also his ‘Of Time and History: The
Dead of War, Memory and the National Imaginary in Timor-Leste’, Communication, Politics &
Culture, vol. 48, no. 3, 2015 pp. 16–28.
82
Paul James
different from what modernists designate as ‘tradition’. Only
modernists invent traditions. In the modern sense, a ‘tradition’ is a
regularised event that gains its power through intense regularised
calendrical repetition. By contrast, traditionalism as described here
is embracing and more broadly constitutive. Traditional events, as
opposed to modern traditions, are, as we will see, meaningful in
relation to the world around us. They are repeated for themselves;
they do not gain meaning simply because they are repeated. In
short, traditionalism draws a cosmological and metaphorical blanket
over relations, events, objects and meanings.
With an orientation towards the cosmological, basic categories of
the human condition — time, space, embodiment, knowledge and
performance — were and are abstracted in relation to something
else, both immanent and beyond (with the emphasis on the
beyond): God, Nature, Form, Being. With an orientation towards
the metaphorical, foundational relations were and are abstracted in
relation to something enclosing and beyond (with the emphasis on
the enclosing): the City of Man, the body politic, the civitas, the res
publica Christiana (with none of these yet constituted as ‘abstract
communities’ in the modern sense). Through these same processes,
Being with a capital ‘B’ is often given metaphoric social resonance:
the singular King on the Day of Judgment; the threefold person of
Father, Son and Holy Ghost; the threefold Lords (Trimurti), their
wives (Tridevi) and their avatars; the eightfold Pathway. This process depends on understanding being through living metaphor. It
requires a very particular way of knowing to proclaim a knowledge
of being in this way.
The theoretical move being made here by the levels argument —
that is, recognising that religion changes with overlaying and
different ontologies of knowing — would, for example, allow a
theologian such as David Bentley Hart to call upon modern reason
to argue that the scriptures should be read allegorically for values
that lie in theistic truths (what I would call cosmological truths), as
opposed to naturalistic truths (analytical modern truths). But it
would avoid his arrogant dismissal of naturalism as unable to
address the ‘being of the whole’, as ‘bordering on a belief in magic
that may be pure prejudice’, and as limited to mapping ‘the ontological poverty of all things physical’.50 Recognising ontologically
50 D. B. Hart, The Experience of God: Being, Consciousness, Bliss, New Haven, Yale University
Press, 2013, pp. 77, 82, 91.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
83
different ways of approaching nature and being suggests, firstly,
that post-customary religions themselves are no longer set at one
constitutive level.51 Secondly, it allows us to see how the nature of
religion changes fundamentally with the dominance of this formation of traditionalism, even as traditional religions incorporate and
reconstitute older customary forms of spirituality. Traditionalism is
the source of what we now call the ‘world religions’ or ‘religions of
the book’. Thirdly, it makes us sensitive to the hubris of the
religions of the book. Those religions had an imperial appetite for
the mythologies of earlier belief systems. For example, there is
much stronger textual evidence from the Bible itself, coupled with
circumstantial evidence from contemporary archeology, that the
ram in the thicket — burned on Abraham’s pyre as a replacement
for his possible sacrifice of Isaac (Genesis 22:13) — was an allegory
for the burning of the old customary gods by Christianity, rather
than a foretelling of the sacrifice of Jesus as the ‘Lamb of God’. In
short, traditionalism can be characterised as carrying forward prior
ontological forms that were foundational to being human, and
reconstituting those forms in terms of new cosmologicalmetaphorical relations — both creatively and destructively.52
The reconstitution of analogical valences through more abstract
metaphorical modes of relating is not a straightforward process to
describe. It is most readily understood through examining the
change in the dominant mode of communication from orality to
writing that characterises one aspect of the shift from customary
tribalism to traditionalism. Writing potentially carries forward all
the sounds and embodied performativity of orality through written
emphasis, rhythm and subsequent translation53 — reading aloud,
theatre and mimesis — but it leaves something unfulfilled. It adds
an abstract layer of increasingly codified language, lifting meaning
out of its immediate embodied context and opening it to wider
51 It is hard for us moderns/postmoderns who have lost empathy with traditional meanings to
understand the power of living metaphor. Religious believers are partial exceptions. An
interesting example here comes from Bruce Barber (Beginning at the Beginning, pp. 14–15).
Writing about the transubstantiation of bread and wine, and drawing upon Aristotle, he
suggests that the objects or accidents of bread and wine do not change, but rather the
intentionality or substance behind the accidents of the bread and the wine. Thus, a modern
understanding of traditional meaning finds a way to use traditional metaphor to make breadas-the-body-of-Christ believable for modern sensibilities.
52 In this, though the genealogical goes through profound cultural-political-economic changes,
it is the most ontologically continuous of all the valences, if only simply because having a
body and being born of a mother remain foundational to traditional life (and, I would
quickly add, to being human).
53 Potentially; but it also loses the embodied presence and engagement of orality and speech.
84
Paul James
connections, but it leaves an indeterminate space.54 In particular, it
opens up a spreading space between voice and text. The more one
enters that space to structure the possible spreading meanings, the
more it requires ontological work — and so generations upon
generations of philosophers, political theorists, literary interpreters
and theologians have been hard at it. Stories once meaningful
because they were told in the presence of others by animating
storytellers now have to be narrated in projected times, just as they
give meaning to time.55 Just as crucially, because written texts are
available for transporting across time, abstracted from their human
scribes, they take on new possibilities. And it is this lifting out of
meaning from embodied, analogical time and space that gives
writing its magical, sometimes sacred, power. In the beginning was
the Word (John 1:1). Logos.56
This methodological argument can be taken in various
directions. One direction is to examine the effect of writing in
different language settings. The alphabets of the ancient Greeks
and Hebrews, the second without vowels, which some have
suggested is linked to the prohibition on saying God’s name,
would appear to be entirely different in cultural terms. However,
both alphabets turn on the capacity, like all writing, to generate a
sense of disembodied agency and authority. Writing thus traditionally projects the possibility of both a universalised authority
beyond the author who merely pens the words or tells the story,
and a universalised reader who defers to the truth of the word.57 In
the world of cosmological and metaphorical abstraction, this universalised author becomes the space for the entry of The Author. As
Brian Rotman suggests, writing puts us ‘beside ourselves’, trying to
hold together embodied gestures and communication with a
disembodied, inscribed ‘I’:
At the beginning of the alphabetic West two figures inhabiting
this description emerged. Two quasi-human agencies, master
ghosts of the alphabet, who/which have since constituted
54 W. J. Ong, Orality and Literacy: The Technologizing of the Word, London, Methuen, 1982.
55 P. Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, Volume 1, Chicago, University of Chicago Press, 1984.
56 With the modern overlay of constructivism, this process is abstracted again, giving rise to the
parallel possibilities of the ‘death of the author’ (Barthes in 1967) and ‘the death of God’
movement (the cover of the 8 April 1966 edition of Time magazine, but going back to
Nietzsche in the nineteenth century.
57 Cf. Heraclitus: ‘Listening not to me, but the logos, it is wise to acknowledge that all is one’.
Heraclitus is the archetypal self-deferring teller of metaphoric-cosmological truths. See E.
Brann, The Logos of Heraclitus, Philadelphia, Paul Dry Books, 2011.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
85
major horizons of Western religious thought and intellectual
discourse came into being. One was God or Jahweh [the God
of ‘I am that I am’], the external mono-being conjured out of
their tribal god [El-ohim, the God that we will meet in a moment who gets his hands dirty] by the Israelites; the other
Mind or psyche/nous, the internal organ of thought conceived
by the Greeks to exist as non-somatic — mental — agency.
These two agencies could not have occurred in more different
social, historical, cultural and intellectual milieus. Nonetheless,
each of the Hebraic and Greek encounters with alphabetic
writing gave rise in the 6th century BCE to a supernatural,
disembodied agency. They did so (as far as is known) independently of each other through the same mediological move
of exploiting and being captured by the ghostly possibilities
inherent in the writing of ‘I’.58
In other words, according to Rotman, God and Mind were both
brought into being as hypostasised effects of the alphabet through
a sense of an ‘I’ and an ‘I am that I am’: Yahweh. As contra-theistic
as that might first appear, the proposition fits the overall argument
presented here, though with two provisos. The first qualification is
that a fuller account would not confine its analysis to writing as a
means of communication. As implied in the surrounding discussion, other modes of practice — production, exchange, organisation,
enquiry — are equally important to the process of abstracting a
sacred Other.59 A longer essay would track the intersection of all
these processes. The second qualification is that the proposition
does not tell us anything about whether or not Yahweh, God, Allah
or the Trimurti actually exist. In the levels approach being presented here, that issue is treated as a question of faith rather than
one of analytical proof or social-theoretical explanation.
All that I am trying to do here — and no more — is point to the
58 B. Rotman, Becoming Beside Ourselves: The Alphabet, Ghosts and the Distributed Human Being,
Durham, Duke University Press, 2008, pp. 120–1.
59 Lest it be thought that I am only referring to religions of the book (though they are a special
case), here is a wonderful example from almost two centuries ago. John Bentley in 1825
writes: ‘We may also see, that Buddha, the son of Mãyã, or the year [a sacred temporal
period], being the founder of a religious sect in India, is a mere fiction, and that we are rather
to take it in a figurative sense; that is to say that time has produced this religion, and that the
person or persons who may have first promulgated it, are now unknown’ (A Historical View
of the Hindu Astronomy from the Earliest Dawn of that Science in India to the Present Time,
London, Smith, Elder and Co., 1825, pp. 60–1). It does not take away from the philosophy of
Buddhism, but it does call into question the ways that its doctrines describe their own
historical beginnings.
86
Paul James
beginnings of a social-theoretical method that can handle the issue
of why people believe in gods or God, and what are the changing
forms that practices and meanings of that belief took across human
history. It might be personally the case that I am more convinced
that the image of God was made in the image of humans rather than
the other way around, but that is not particularly relevant. And
many contemporary theologians would agree. The Otherness of
God is ineffable — completely other — and therefore how can we
know of His image? I do not contest the possibility that my theological colleagues writing in this volume are right about the existence
of a God and that He made humanity in His image. However, if I
were them I would put the emphasis on the faith rather than what
God actually is or does, other than that he is utterly Other. In any
case, the existence or otherwise of God is irrelevant to this
approach, and this cuts both ways. By the definition of religion
posed earlier, radical atheism may not be a religion, but it is as
much a faith claim as theism — except that it is a less cogent one.
Going back to ‘time’ as our example again, we can see how the
process is much broader than just within the mode of communication, just about an abstract ‘I’, or even about faith alone. For
Christians and Muslims alike, the times of the past, present and
future become cosmologically interrelated through an omnitemporal being, with the past becoming a foretelling of what is to
come, mediated through the present. Linking this to writing in the
biblical tradition, the centre point of time is God’s word.
Ecclesiastes 3:1 provides a classic rendition: ‘To everything there is
a season, and a time for every purpose under heaven: a time to be
born and a time to die …’. The older analogical sense of seasonal
time features in the first phrase referring to seasons, but immediately it is reframed by the cosmological understanding of ‘under
heaven’, before returning to the older sense of time, this time
genealogical. This process is close to what different lineages of
writers — including Benedict Anderson and Giorgio Agamben,
both via Walter Benjamin and all steeped in the Jewish/Christian
traditions — narrowly call ‘Messianic time’. However, the concept
of the ‘Messianic’ does not work for our purposes for a number of
reasons. Firstly, it signifies only one aspect of time, sacred
Christian/Jewish time. Paul’s term for ‘Messianic time’ in the first
century is ho nym kairos, the time of what is now remaining. But this
was distinguished even then from chronological time (ordinary
time) and eschatological or apocalyptic time (the time of the
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
87
anticipated sacred end).60 Our definition of the traditional rests on
a more embracing sense of time as the given immanent/transcendental location of all being, including all times, ordinary and
revelatory.
Secondly, the concept needs to be relevant to other traditions
beyond the Abrahamic religions and their proclamation of an actual
or possible Messiah. Hinduism is culturally different in a multitude
of ways from Christianity and Judaism, but at the level of discussing
basic categories of existence we find fundamental convergences.
Redolent of the way in which the Christian God is present ‘in the
beginning’, so also Krishna is time: ‘I am time’, he says, ‘bringing
about the destruction of the world’. Taoism treats time as eternal,
an all-embracing infinite Void. Hindu time, linked to creation,
preservation and destruction, moves through unfolding cycles —
ages — both repeating themselves and open to change through the
play (lilãì) of multiple deities and the activities of humans.61
Similarly, traditional Islamic theology links time to Allah. There are
numerous writings, charts and diagrams linking days of the week
with letters of the alphabet and the divine names of Allah.62 There
is possibly one lineage of one religion that does not fit this argument, namely Zen Buddhism. However, even here time becomes
being itself: being-time.
In these senses, traditional time is cosmological time in all its
amazing variants, brought down to earth in different ways by
metaphorical considerations. This tension between cosmological
time (singular, even if there are many gods, devas and avatars — or,
practices and ways) and different metaphorical times (plural, given
the open possibilities of abstracted language), although with the
same ontological frame, sets up cultural contradictions that
philosophers steeped in traditional life needed and need to resolve.
Here the concept of cultural contradiction — or economic or political
contradiction (these are all kinds of social contradictions) — refers
to basic tensions occurring within a particular ontological formation, while the concept of ontological contradiction refers to basic contradictions occurring between ontological formations. Augustine’s
60 G. Agamben, The Time that Remains: A Commentary on the Letter to the Romans, Stanford,
Stanford University Press, 2005, p. 61.
61 J. Lipner, Hindus: Their Religion, Beliefs and Practices, London, Routledge, 1994, chapter 10,
‘Modes of Reckoning Time and “Progress”’; R. Kloetzli and A. Hiltebeitel, ‘Kãla’, in S. Mittal
and G. Thursby (eds), The Hindu World, New York, Routledge, 2004.
62 M. H. Yousef, Ibn ‘Arabi: Time and Cosmology, London, Routledge, 2008.
88
Paul James
Confessions provides us with an anguished example of how a
philosopher-theologian from the fifth century handles the cultural
contradictions of traditional temporality: the tension between
distentio animi (the extension of the self into multiple temporal
worlds) in a difficult relation with the non-being of time and
intentio (intention in time) linked to the striving for eternity.63 This
was never a problem for customary philosophers for whom time
was always variously embodied in persons, spirits and things. For
Augustine, the only answer is God.
Writing a millennium and a half later, Karl Barth similarly finds
a way through the problem by distinguishing between ‘Godcreated time’ and ‘our time’, and then finding a third time that
brings both together: the body of Jesus Christ. This revelatory
embodied event occurs both in our ‘historical’ time and God’s
time.64 Thus Christ’s body offers a soteriological synthesis of the
transcendental and immanent. Jesus Christ, truly human but born
of the Spirit of God, provides a perfect example here. Jesus is simultaneously God, God-Incarnate, and an embodied mortal man. He
is Mary Douglas’s boundary-crosser extraordinaire, sacred because
he binds together in one body the cultural contradictions that
inhere in struggling with the profane and the sacred.65
At the risk of repeating my argument too often, this is one of the
things that a constitutive levels method allows us to show: namely,
how religion finds its deep cosmological meanings and metaphorical expressions in both the cultural and ontological contradictions
of the human condition. To be blunt, what I am arguing is that our
interpretations of Jesus are born of the cultural and ontological
contradictions of Jesus’s time and the intensifying ontological contradictions that build across the ensuing 2000 years as traditional
and modern ways of life overlaid, and to some extent displaced,
traditional and tribal formations from the centre of social power.
Thus, in political terms, while I personally do not follow the
notion that Jesus is the way, I do understand that at one level of being
for the Christian-with-faith this is exactly what has to be posited for
that religion not to be emptied out of its reason for being. I am thus
not suggesting that Christians should give up on that belief. What I
63 Ricoeur, Time and Narrative, chapter 1; M. Drever, Image, Identity and the Forming of the
Augustine Soul, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2013.
64 K. Barth, Church Dogmatics, 1.2: The Doctrine of the Word of God, London, T&T Clark, 1956,
section 14, ‘The Time of Revelation’, pp. 45–70, cited from p. 47.
65 M. Douglas, Implicit Meanings: Selected Essays in Anthropology, London, Routledge, 1999.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
89
am arguing for is a reflexive understanding by people of faith that
the originating traditional belief about ‘the way’ (singular) needs to
be held in self-conscious and public contradiction with the view
that there is no one true way. In modern/postmodern terms, a
christian qua Christian (just like a muslim qua Muslim) can only
make a truth-claim socially. In traditional/modern/postmodern
terms, the sociality of being human gives none of us prior access to
the one and only truth. This move, I suggest, can be done without
resorting to empty relativism. It is a matter of being reflexive
ontologically about where one stands as one makes a claim.
The same argument about temporality and embodiment (and
specifically the temporal event of Jesus’s body) can be made in the
domain of spatiality. Contradictions beset religions, as they do all
of us, as they/we attempt to resolve the relationship between
transcendental and immanent space. The bounds of traditional
religious meaning are potentially limitless, or, to be more precise,
they are both immanent in, and transcendent of, spatiality: ‘In the
beginning God created the heaven and the earth. And the earth was
without form and void’.66 In that passage, written down by a
cosmologically framed ‘priestly’ tradition, we see the transcendental
nature of God — being, before time and space. But in a second story
in Genesis told by an earlier analogically driven school of thinkers,
we see the immanent effect of the creator God — being in time and
space. He is in the earth, getting his hands dirty, and making the
bodies of man and woman. This tension at the centre of Genesis
seems to be only the stuff of sophisticated theologians, but it needs
to be part of the common sense of Christian believers. Contradiction is not a negative thing; handled creatively, contradiction is
the material of life and death.
All of the world’s religions contend with these contradictions,
some more intensely than others. We could ask ‘How are they
resolved?’. Alternatively, we could pursue the question as to why
some actual places are sacred when all of Yahweh’s, God’s and
Allah’s creations are transcendentally placed. And, why in the
journey of enlightened Buddhists are all places left behind?
Particular places come to be held as sacred because they become
sites of condensed contradiction — the River Ganges in Hinduism,
the Holy Land of Judaism, the Stations of the Cross or the Holy See
for Catholic Christians, Mecca and Medina for Muslims, and the
66 The opening passage of the Christian and Judaic Bible: Genesis 1:1–2.
90
Paul James
Temple of the Tooth for Sinhalese Buddhists. In the monotheistic
religions, such places bring the fundamentally, essentially, absolutely
transcendent down to earth — much as the body of Jesus does for
temporality. In Buddhism, they become sacred places pointing the
way to travellers on the way to being non-placed.
Augustine thus posited, for example, a distinction between the
City of God as wholly divine in nature and the Earthly City as the
base-worldly polity. What was most important for him was the City
of God, but this sets up a major issue. An apparent Manichean tension
— an actual cultural contradiction between absolute transcendence
and lived immanence — confronts Christianity, just as it confronts
Islam. For Augustine, it is solved in the following argument: part of
the City of God also sojourns on earth and lives by faith.67 What I
am arguing politically is for an extension (with a twist) of this
sacred but unsatisfactory reconciliation. To the extent that we live
in a world characterised by the intersection of different ontological
formations, it can be said that part of the City of Humanity lives by
faith in the City of God, but only at one level of their being, and
only through reflexive recognition that it could be otherwise.
The Modern as an Ontological Formation
The modern is defined by the way in which prior valences of social
life — analogical, genealogical, mythological, cosmological and metaphorical relations — are reconstituted through a constructivist reframing of social practices in relation to basic categories of existence
common to all humans: time, space, embodiment, performance and
knowledge.68 The word ‘reconstituted’ here explicitly does not mean
replaced. Prior valences continue on, even if framed by the new
ontological dominance of constructivist meanings and practices.
In constructivist terms, these basic categories of human existence
become the terrain of different projects to be made and remade,
thought and rethought anew. Bodies, landscapes, genome systems,
aesthetic principles and political systems become projects for
construction and reconstruction. From the rise of the divided public
67 Augustine of Hippo, The City of God, Peabody, Hendrickson Publishers, 2009, book 19,
chapter 17.
68 It seems uncomfortable to take only one additional social theme to have our definition of the
modern turn upon when previously we used three themes for customary formations and
two additional themes for traditionalism. However, it seems to be enough for our purposes.
Given the methodological principles of simple usefulness and sufficient complexity, I am
currently going with it while remaining open to better suggestions.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
91
self in eighteenth-century England and France69 to the globalised
autonomous self of the twenty-first century, even the self becomes
an object of projected construction.
Other writers have suggested related themes for the basis of
their definitions of the modern. In one of his takes on a definition,
Zygmunt Bauman makes reflexivity central to its meaning: ‘We can
think of modernity as of a time when order — of the world, of the
human habitat, of the human self, and of the connection between
all three — is reflected upon … conscious of being a conscious
practice’.70 This is to focus on a single ontology as the basis of the
definition, namely the social form of knowing. In another take, he
says it is ordering divided: ‘We can say that the existence is modern
in as far as it forks into order and chaos. The existence is modern in
as far as it contains the alternative of order and chaos. Indeed: order
and chaos, full stop’.71 This take fails completely: the order–chaos
distinction is redolent through many traditional religions. In
another, he says that it is design that distinguishes the modern:
‘The existence is modern insofar as it is guided by the urge of
designing what otherwise would not be there: designing of itself’.72
Each of these definitions is within a couple of pages of each other
in a single book, and he is not playing a game. It illustrates the
difficulty of defining something so basic. The (tertiary) valence of
‘constructivism’ has been chosen to encompass those themes: a
reflexive, restless drive to construct and remake the world, nature
and ourselves because we have no choice but to choose what they
and we should look like.
The present method with its emphasis on reconstitution of forms
rather than replacement of epochs also helps to make sense of
Bruno Latour’s counterintuitive argument that we have never been
modern: ‘No one has ever been modern’, he says. ‘Modernity has
never begun. There has never been a modern world … we have
never left the old anthropological matrix behind.’73 Apart from
enjoying the shock value of heresy in a world dominated by
modern self-congratulation, Latour’s primary concern is that the
modern sets up a great divide between the natural and the social,
and then offers to translate between them through science. And,
69
70
71
72
73
R. Sennett, The Fall of Public Man, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1977.
Z. Bauman, Modernity and Ambivalence, Cambridge, Polity Press, 1991, p. 5.
Bauman, Modernity and Ambivalence, p. 6.
Bauman, Modernity and Ambivalence, p. 7.
B. Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1993, p. 67.
Paul James
92
indeed, it does in the relative occlusion of the embedded analogical.
However, contra Latour and Bauman, and so on, the method
being developed in this essay puts the emphasis on the reconstitution of ontologically complex forms, and handles this
contradiction by showing how prior forms live on in the swirling
currents of the new. And it does so without sounding either ornery
for its own sake, or refusing to recognise that we are in this time
dominated across the globe by a formation that can contingently be
called ‘modernity’. Of particular relevance here is that analogical
relations between the natural and social, dominant under
conditions of the customary, have been in many ways redefined or
blustered aside. They are subordinated, for example, in terms of the
dominion over an external nature that needs to be subdued
(expressed strongly in both traditional Christian and Jewish
liturgy), or later in terms of the reconstruction and reconstitution of
nature (expressed as liberation by modern and postmodern
science). This is the first major difference in method between the
levels approach and Latour’s Actor Network Theory. The second
difference in method is that his approach emphasises continuity:
Seen as networks, however, the modern world, the revolutions, permits scarcely anything but small extensions of practices, slight accelerations in the circulation of knowledge, a
tiny extension of societies, minuscule increases in the number
of actors, small modifications of old beliefs.74
This seems to be simply empirically wrong. By comparison, the
levels approach understands change in terms of a dialectic of
continuity and discontinuity. This allows, on the one hand, for the
recognition of the comprehensiveness of the new crises that we face
in the contemporary world, including the increasingly disembedded sense of our relationship to nature. On the other hand,
this same abstracted relationship to nature leaves us floundering to
do anything systematic in response to the potential of a calamitous
climate-change crisis as it continues to creep up on us.
The issue of crisis takes us back to our example of time. Time in
traditional senses was (is) often described metaphorically — it
travels like an arrow, it is spaced like knots on a long string, and it
flows like a river, all understood in terms of something beyond
itself — but in modernity (that is, in places and times when the
74 Latour, We Have Never Been Modern, p. 48.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
93
modern is dominant), time becomes itself. The emergence of such a
level of temporality leads us in two simultaneous directions: the
first is subjectivism, for example as expressed by Immanuel Kant,
for whom time was the foundation of all experience. The second is
objectivism, expressed by Isaac Newton in 1687 as giving the
possibility of ‘Absolute, true, and mathematical time, of itself, and
from its own nature, [flowing] equally without relation to anything
external’.75 Both converged on the notion of time as time-in-itself,
natural with a small ‘n’, and unable to be defined beyond itself.
This broad process affects all ontological categories and
dethrones both of the dominant entities that once gave them
meaning: God and Nature. Time becomes the medium of passing
or lost moments, mapped day by day onto empty calendrical grids.
In positive terms, this is the form of temporality that allows for
creative historicity. It sensitises politics. That is, it leaves space for
reflection upon ‘historical time’ as it is measured (tautologously)
across time and space. But it is also a form of time in which, paradoxically, crisis consciousness becomes endemic while actual crises
lose their generality and ontological force. Crises become contested
points in history. The postmodern takes this one stage further to
where social life is reframed in terms of contested standpoints — a
kind of relativism that I would argue even fragments the possibility
of politically projecting other worlds.
The Postmodern as an Ontological Formation
The postmodern is defined by the way in which prior valences of
social life — analogical, genealogical, mythological, cosmological,
metaphorical and constructivist — are reconstituted through a
relativist reframing of social practices in relation to basic categories
of existence common to all humans. In relativist terms, these basic
categories of the human are all open for deconstruction. One of the
strengths of the postmodern is that it relativises the certainties of
the modern (although it should be quickly added that modern
constructivism already continually undermines its own certainties,
albeit always in favour of new ones). The strengths of relativising
knowledge are profound — indeed the present analysis benefits from
the insights of deconstructive analysis and postmodern critique.
75 Both examples, including the quote, are from S. Kern, The Culture of Time and Space, 1880–
1918, Cambridge, Harvard University Press, 1983, p. 11.
94
Paul James
The problem arises when the postmodern comes into ontological
predominance. In practice, to the extent that it serves to undermine
any standpoint that would argue against the dominance of a
relativising epistemology, postmodernism becomes the metaideology for the deconstruction of the planet, figuratively and
literally. If there is no nature, except for the nature that we project
upon stones, plants and animals (a problem for the new materialists), then there are no grounds for deciding on what is right or
good in relation to nature. What we do with our own projections
becomes a question of agonistic interrogation. There become no
stable reference points to guide how humans negotiate the nature–
culture contradiction, let alone how we act in and on nature. With
the dominance of postmodern science, all deconstruction becomes
simultaneously agonistically contested and essentially uncontestable, including the deconstruction and recombining of the basic
elements of nature from atoms to genes.
In postmodern religion, the sacred becomes similarly an
aesthetic agonistic projection, depending upon the standpoint of
the participant. And in postmodern politics, projections of alternatives are constantly relativised and displaced in favour of constant deconstruction, allowing for new appeals to what is now
called ‘post-truth’ — the time of Trump, Le Pen and Dawkins. It is
no coincidence that the genre of modern utopia is now treated as
anachronistic in all but a couple of discrete fields. Thus, the
substantial and important strengths of postmodern values and
practices become the basis for its (and our) deconstruction.
Instead of developing an extended treatment of the postmodern,
there is sufficient evidence in that brief discussion to proceed to a
conclusion about the consequences of all of the foregoing discussion for an ethics of human flourishing. Postmodernism as a
social form carries its own ideologies of transcendence. Against
those such as Taylor who suggest, firstly, that there is something
special in seeking the transcendental and, secondly, that a poetry of
faith sensitises us to the problems inherent in the late modern/
postmodern turn, I want to argue that religion is very much in the
world (even though its believers claim that their belief is not of the
world). Religion faces all the tensions and contradictions of the
ontological layering of analogical, genealogical, mythological,
cosmological, metaphorical, constructivist and relativist valences
that I have been describing, and does so in much the way that all
social phenomena do.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
95
Postmodern time, for example, relativises the standpoint from
which time-for-itself — empty modern time — can do its thing in
the background while we fill it with (self-constructed) meaning.
This, too, has found its unstable expression as Christian physicists
argue for the return of a God that is no longer in the machine.
Quantum mechanics and God can now be projected as an aesthetic
fit. In practical terms and expressed more generally, postmodern
(and, ironically, neo-traditionalising) versions of Christianity find
their cultural resonance in exactly those same theoretical transformations that Taylor is saying replaced the religious sensibility
and brought about the emptying out of the human condition.
Conclusion: What Does This All Mean for an Ethics
of Human Flourishing?76
A parallel history and comparative social mapping could be written for the changing dominant levels of ethical abstraction: different
ways of thinking about what is ‘good’ and what is ‘right’. Put most
briefly, it is possible to show that, like other social practices, the
nature of different ethical systems is patterned upon the nature of
the society in which they are lived and contested. At the risk of
oversimplifying a long and incredibly complex intertwined history
of different ethical approaches, it is useful to analytically distinguish a number of dominant modalities in relation to different
dominant ontological formations: analogical ethics, cosmological
ethics, constructivist ethics and relativist ethics. The first — analogical ethics — is dominant in customary societies, although it has
residual and subordinate relevance in all societies. Analogical
ethics emphasises the right way to sustain embodied relations
between persons and persons, and between persons and things —
sacred and banal objects, places, features of the landscape, animal
species and forces of nature. It is the kind of ethics reinterpreted in
living narratives by customary storytellers on the basis of what
has been handed down to them. The implicit emphasis is on care,
reciprocity and mutuality, without necessarily abstracting these
practical-sacred relations into reflexively applied principles. The
integrative relations carried by each telling work to revivify, reconfirm and reproduce the integrative force of face-to-face relations:
76 The paragraphs in this section have been reworked from an earlier attempt to do something
similar: P. James, ‘Theory in the Shadow of Terror: Mapping an Alternative’, Alternatives:
Global, Local, Political, vol. 30, no. 3, 2005, pp. 365–88.
96
Paul James
that is, facing other persons and embodying the self as part of the
circle of nature. This provides one form of an ethics of foundations
grounded in the mutuality of the social and natural.
The second major form — cosmological ethics — abstracts from
analogical ethics by locating the source of meaning somewhere
other than within the perceptually and analogically known socialnatural relationships themselves. If, for example, in Navajo or
Yolngu tribal culture the life-sustaining relation between mother
and child provides the actual foundation for all bonds of kinship,
social and natural,77 then in Christian traditional culture the
mother-and-Christ-child image refers to the sacred life that is
transcendental and removed from the lives of mere mortals and, at
the same time, returned to the flesh as a sustaining lived metaphor
of the exemplary-sacred. The Saviour, by Quirizio da Murano, for
example, shows Christ with one hand opening his wounded chest
where a nipple would be found, and with the other hand feeding a
Eucharist wafer to a kneeling nun.78 Thus, the painters tell us, He is
the way and the life. He is the lived metaphoric embodiment of
how relational ethics should work. His body is the source and He
is the provider. Cosmological ethics provides a more abstract way
of approaching an ethics of foundations. It still tries to get to the
bottom of the meaning of life, but it abstracts analogical ethics in
three ways: firstly, it finds exemplary carriers of meaning (such as
Jesus, Buddha, Mohammed); secondly, it begins to codify rules for
living that are written outside the stories of the law-givers (the Ten
Commandments, halacha, sharia, dharma, and so on); and thirdly,
it begins to reflect upon an ethics of care through homilies. Do unto
others as you would have them do unto you, and the like.
Whether we refer to Islam, Christianity or Confucianism as
examples, the universalising religions of the book all treat ethics as
that which is both metaphorically embodied and codifiable. An
ethics of care is subordinated to the speaker of homilies. Care and
its codification occur through intellectually mediated reflection
upon the meaning of a transcendent God, transcendent Nature or
transcendent Law. Sometimes the right and the good were passed
on by God-sustained edict, such as when Moses was handed the
two stone tablets containing the Ten Commandments, or some77 See A. L. Peterson, Being Human: Ethics, Environment and Our Place in the World, Berkeley,
University of California Press, 2001, chapter 5.
78 C. W. Bynum, Holy Feast and Holy Fast, Berkeley, University of California Press, 1987, plate
2.25.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
97
times they were enshrined in natural law, beginning with the Greek
philosophers such as Aristotle in his Nicomachean Ethics, but they
were almost always constituted in the overlaying of forms.79
This brings us to the third more abstract kind of ethics,
constructivist ethics, of which rationalised impartial ethics is one
expression. Constructivist ethics was able, more or less, to stand
alone by the eighteenth century, even if many documents such as
Thomas Paine’s The Rights of Man still appealed to natural law.
Contemporary constructivism takes processes of codification a step
further, and at the same time makes possible an alternative
pathway that is critical of its own rationalism. The lineage of
constructivism came self-consciously to project an ‘ethics of care’,
but care took a subordinate place in a crowded literature of ethics
dominated by liberal rationalism: for example, liberal rights theory,
utilitarian ethics and liberal cosmopolitanism. The dominant kind
of cosmopolitanism today, abstracted cosmopolitanism, is
grounded in the intellectual force of abstracted modern rationality
(or, as a second-order claim, in the reality of the globalisation of
politics in the contemporary period). In an attempt to get beyond
subjectivism, abstract cosmopolitanism in its different manifestations sought different methods of rational grounding. One
contemporary voice of this kind of cosmopolitanism is rationalist
cosmopolitanism. It is best represented by extensions of John Rawls’s
liberal theory of justice.80 Rationalism of this kind projects a hypothetical abstracted condition where a group of unknown individuals,
shorn of any particular attachments, can supposedly impartially
decide on what are good principles. They thus ground their ethics
in an abstracted condition of social ‘neutrality’ and ‘emptiness’
rather than a metaphorical dialogue with others or nature.
Thus, for mainstream modern rationalised ethics, rules and rights
— now no longer embedded in cosmologies — become things in
themselves. Human-rights regimes, including the Millennium
Development Goals, are the paramount modern examples today,
with all their strengths and problems. Their problems derive from
the intensification and dominance of the codification process.
Unfortunately, modern desires to code, monitor and measure
outcomes tend to subordinate prior ethics of foundations. In the
process, they sideline an ethics of care to the concerns of indivi79 A. Vincent, Theories of the State, Oxford, Basil Blackwell, 1987, chapter 3.
80 J. Rawls, A Theory of Justice, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 1999.
98
Paul James
duals in their private moments, occasional acts of extraordinary
kindness or public rhetorical flourishes.
In the context of the broader ontological emergence described
earlier, there has emerged a fourth form of ethics, relativist ethics. It
is characterised by agonism — that is, the agonising from different
standpoints over the relative value of different actions and
practices. Such agonism emerged as an important social modality
in the twentieth century as professional philosophers of ethics
increasingly began to relativise old ethical verities and lay
intellectuals increasingly interrogated the grounding assumptions
of modern regimes of justice and rights. In the twenty-first century,
it became the terrain of private self-reflection for those who care but
do not quite know what to do about it.
All the while, cosmological ethics has maintained a continuing
but often reconstituted force into the present. In many areas of life,
it has shaded into, been overwhelmed by or become distorted by
constructivist ethics. When this intersection of ethical valences is
not handled well, it becomes a potential source of horror. The
overlaying of forms can even be seen in purifying movements such
as Wahhabite Islam, arguably, alongside modern intellectual
training, one of the strongest influences on the terrorism of Osama
bin Laden.81 Aziz Al-Azmeh sets this out in its complexity, showing
how Islamic fundamentalisms tend to look back to an exemplary
cosmology while paradoxically (flexibly) hardening traditional
scripture as modern constructed law:
It purports to detail the exemplary behaviour of the Prophet
and his contemporaries, and to utilise this register of exemplaries as a character for reform. The fundamentals of rectitude
are contained in this register, and the history that intervenes
between the occurrence of the exemplary acts and today is an
accident that no more than sullies and corrupts its origin, and
which therefore can be eliminated, as history is the mere passage
of time … [The scriptural and the historical-contemporary] are
set in parallel registers and are expressed in terms of today’s
fundamentally right bearings, making the iniquities of today
less historical realities than supervening mistakes that can be
eliminated by reference to exemplary precedent … 82
81 J. L. Esposito, Unholy War: Terror in the Name of Islam, Oxford, Oxford University Press, 2002,
pp. 5–6, 73.
82 A. Al-Azmeh, Islams and Modernities, London, Verso, 2nd edition, 1996, pp. 151–2.
What Does It Mean Ontologically to Be Religious?
99
Christian fundamentalism is no less worrying.
Buried in the discussion of ethics and ontological formations,
including the problems of intersecting modalities, are lessons about
what the overlaying of social forms means for an alternative
politics. It appears that by historicising everything, including
ethics, my argument ends up caught between a modernist
reflexivity and a postmodern relativising of certainty. The tensions
are actually more comprehensive than that. What I am arguing is
that the grounding of being human is no more and no less than our
glorious and inglorious time on this planet from the customary to
the postmodern. Yahweh, God, Allah or the Trimurti may or may
not exist, but given the contemporary crisis, turning to any one of
them as the way is unlikely to provide guidance as to what is to be
done. Given that we have become the authors of our own potential
destruction, the work of negotiating our future remains ours. And
this needs to be done by reflecting seriously on the tensions and
contradictions of the past and present.
Ethically it will require going back to basics — an ethics of
foundations, qualified but not overshadowed or reconstituted in
terms of more abstract modalities. That is, by going back across the
valences of practice and meaning that have across human history
given us our humanness there is a chance that we will find a
sustainable and vibrant way of living on this planet. Practically it
will entail a revolution in practice that seeks to draw out the
strengths of each of the valences of the human condition into a
syncretic ethics of care. This does not mean going back to ways of
life or some of their cultural expressions that first gave rise to those
valences. That is neither possible (except romantically) nor
meaningful. Rather it requires a leap of commitment of a different
kind than asked for by the religions of the world:
First it means leaping to reconceptualise ‘the world’ and reforming ourselves within this new understanding. This is nothing
to do with redrawing the geopolitical map and everything to
do with repositioning ourselves within our mode of being-inthe-world. It is about seeing ourselves as conduits connected
to object-things, animals and human Others, dwelling in
every respect in mind and matter. This leap effectively folds
into a continual act of a self-world re-creation and remaking (a
generalised and unending project of ontological design that
learns from how we came into being as an indivisible self/
world-formation construction) … [W]hatever affirmative
Paul James
100
change can be created, we cannot be sure that it will not
emanate from an abstract system, no matter of what order or
how formulated. Change here can be but the overcoming of
nihilism — a designing out of a created wasteland.83
As both Tony Fry in this passage and Charles Taylor in his work
have argued, ‘Much of our deep past cannot be simply laid aside,
not because of our “weakness”, but because there is something
important and valuable in it’.84 We cannot go back, but our future
depends upon ontological learning from this alterity. Thus, from
very different methodological approaches we have ended up in a
similar place. However, from the perspective of the argument
presented in this essay, it is not a critique or an understanding of
the secular that is central to meditating on what should be done.
What is central is rather the question of how we are to negotiate
different modes of being and their different valences. Responding
to the immanent frame may be one small part of that process, but
part of the larger task is working out what it means to be human.
83 T. Fry, Becoming Human by Design, London, Berg Publishers, 2012, p. 114.
84 Taylor, A Secular Age, p. 771.