Jump to content

Fa (philosophy)

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Fa
Chinese
Literal meaningstandard, model, example, measure, norm, way, solution, rule, method, technique (shu), regulation, protocol, statute, law. to imitate; to emulate.
Transcriptions
Standard Mandarin
Hanyu Pinyin
Small seal scripts were standardized by Li Si after the First Emperor of China gained control of the country, evolving from the larger seal scripts of previous dynasties.

The 12 characters on this slab of floor brick affirm that it is an auspicious moment for the First Emperor to ascend the throne, as the country is united and no men will be dying along the road.

Fa is a concept in Chinese philosophy that concerns aspects of ethics, logic, and law. Although it can be accurately translated as 'law' in some contexts,[1] especially modern Chinese,[2] it refers to a 'model' or 'standard' for the performance of behavior in most ancient texts, namely the Mozi, with a prominent example including the performance of carpentry.[3] Although theoretically earlier, Fa comes to prominence in the Mohist school of thought. An administrative use of fa standards is prominently elaborated in Legalism, but the school of names also used fa (models) for litigation. Given its broadness, the term fa even included medical models (theories).[4]

Fa was still considered important by Warring States period Confucians. Xunzi, whose work would ultimately be foundational to Confucian philosophy during the Han dynasty, took up fa, suggesting that standards could only be properly assessed by the Confucian sage (; shèng), and that the most important fa were the very rituals that Mozi had ridiculed for their ostentatious waste and lack of benefit for the people at large.[5]

In Han Fei's philosophy, the king is the sole source of fa (including 'law'), taught to the common people so that there would be a harmonious society free of chance occurrences, disorder, and "appeal to privilege". High officials were not to be held above the fa, nor were they allowed to independently create their own fa, uniting both executive fiat and rule of law.[6]

Despite a usage by Shang Yang including penal law, in Imperial China fa more commonly referred to government institutions, such as for agricultural loans, than to law per se.[7] The Qin dynasty differentiated the body of statues under the term lu 律, though lu does include a similar root meaning of measurement. Originally referring to the pitch pipe, the meaning of lu refers to a chromatic scale subdividing four solar seasons as twelve, with much of Qin law being administrative.[8]

Mohism

[edit]

The concept of fa first gained importance in the Mohist school of thought. To Mozi, a standard must stand "three tests" in order to determine its efficacy and morality.[9] The first of these tests was its origin, as to whether the standard had precedence in the actions or thought of the mythological sage kings of the Xia dynasty, whose examples are frequently cited in classical Chinese philosophy. The second test was one of validity; does the model stand up to evidence in the estimation of the people? The third and final test was one of applicability; this final one is a utilitarian estimation of the net good that, if implemented, the standard would have on both the people and the state.[10]

The third test speaks to the fact that to the Mohists, a fa was not simply an abstract model, but an active tool. The real-world use and practical application of fa were vital. Yet fa as models were also used in later Mohist logic as principles used in deductive reasoning. As classical Chinese philosophical logic was based on analogy rather than syllogism, fa were used as benchmarks to determine the validity of logical claims through comparison. There were three fa in particular that were used by these later Mohists to assess such claims, which were mentioned earlier. The first was considered a "root" standard, a concern for precedence and origin. The second, a "source", a concern for empiricism. The third, a "use", a concern for the consequence and pragmatic utility of a standard. These three fa were used by the Mohists to both promote social welfare and denounce ostentation or wasteful spending.[11]

Mohist and Confucian fa

[edit]

Described with reference to the square, compass or plumb-line, Mozi used fa in the sense of models and standards for copy and imitation in action. As in Confucianism, Mozi's ruler is intended to act as the fa (or example) for the nobles and officials. From this, the concept of fa develops towards political technique.

Illustrated by the scale, grain-leveler and ink and line, together with a benevolent heart, Mencius's ruler will not achieve effective results without fa. A late contemporary of Shen Buhai and Shang Yang, Mencius's fa more broadly represents models, exemplars and names. Amongst other categories, including techniques of the heart-mind, Mencius's fa includes more specific examples of physical statistics such as temperatures, volumes, consistencies, weights, sizes, densities, distances, and quantities.

Xunzi's notion of fa arguably derives from Confucian li as applied to the regulation of human behavior. The Great Appendix or Ten Wings of the Book of Changes, added by Confucian scholars during the Western Han dynasty, defines fa as "to institute something so that we can use it."[12]

[edit]

Taking Shang Yang as representative, Chapter 43 of the Han Feizi considered fa (standards) necessary, as including law, decrees, reward and punishment, as well as administrative standards (fa) controlled by the ruler, representative of his own state's Shen Buhai. The latter he terms (shu 术) administrative Method or Technique,[13] defined as examining the abilities of ministers, appointing candidates in accordance with their capabilities, and holding ministerial achievements (xing "forms") accountable to their proposals (ming "names").[14]

A legal and administrative use of fa (standards) by the ruler has been argued different mainly in that early religious Mohist's ideal was the universally beneficial sun, as an objective standard of comparison.[15] Although dealing in questions of language, in addition to early supernatural elements, Mozi's concept was not simply an abstract standard, but implied measurement, and were often measurement-like standards, including the plumb-line and carpenters square.[16] In this sense, although Mohism does promote following a virtuous ruler, the Mohist concept of the standard is not a freely determined law simply invented by the ruler. It implies and intends measurement against objective standards. But the Mohists also used standards in engineering and language, and many later Mohist engineers were not necessarily very religious, following the ideals of a pragmatic philosophy.

Although Shang Yang was criticized for harsh punishment, and have philosophical differences, his legal usage is otherwise at least arguably comparable in function to the Mohist usage, promulgating standards (laws) of comparison for people to follow. Xunzi's usage is arguably most different, arguing for the Confucian scholar as interpreter of standards. Shang Yang and Mozi's standards were intended to be understandable by common people. Shang Yang and Han Fei ultimately fall back on the ruler as an authority for determining standards, but Han Fei still intends the ruler try to make objective measurements, to protect him against factors like deceit. Han Fei's ruler may have different objects, but if he tries to make measurements to make objective standards, their concept of the standard can still functionally be compared to Mozi's at least in that sense. It's process is functionally different to the degree the standard is determined arbitrarily.

See also

[edit]

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Pines 2023.
  2. ^ Goldin 2011, p. 91.
  3. ^ Schwartz 1985 p321, Hansen 1992
  4. ^ Loewe 1999 Cambridge p321
  5. ^ Robins, Dan (Fall 2008). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Xunzi". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  6. ^ Han Fei. (2003). Basic Writings. Columbia University Press: New York, p. 7, 21- 28, 40, 91
  7. ^ Goldin 2011.
  8. ^ Loewe 1986.
  9. ^ "College of Letters, Arts and Social Sciences".
  10. ^ Mozi. (2003). Basic Writings. Burton Watson, Ed. Columbia University Press: New York, p. 122
  11. ^ Fraser, Chris (Summer 2010). Zalta, Edward N. (ed.). "Mohism". The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
  12. ^ * Creel 1974 p148. Shen Pu-hai https://books.google.com/books?id=Lw9hEAAAQBAJ&pg=PA262
  13. ^ Creel 1970, p. 81,93-95,103; Goldin 2011, p. 95-96,104,105(7-8,16-17); Hansen 1992, pp. 364, 347, 350; Graham 1989, p. 268,282-283; Pines 2024, p. 58-59,61; Jiang 2021, p. 235.
  14. ^ Makeham 1994, pp. 68, 70; Goldin 2011, p. 98(10).
  15. ^ Kejian 2016; Fraser 2011.
  16. ^ Pines 2024, p. 552.

Sources

[edit]