 Ad Hominem and Related Fallacies
Abstract: The ad hominem fallacy occurs whenever
the character or circumstances of an individual who is advancing an argument
is criticized instead of seeking to disprove the argument provided.
Ad hominem and related argument types including ad
personam, tu quoque, ex concessis,
ex aliquem, poisoning the well, guilt by association,
ad feminam, and genetic fallacies are also studied, and
examples are described in both their fallacious and nonfallacious uses.
The Ad Hominem Abusive and
Circumstantial Fallacies Described
Ad Hominem Fallacy: (abusive and circumstantial):
the fallacy of attacking the character or circumstances of an
individual who is advancing a statement or an argument instead
of seeking to disprove the truth of the statement or the soundness
of the argument.
Often the fallacy is characterized simply as a personal attack. However,
a personal attack is a claim, not a fallacy. Thus, a character or a
circumstantial attack simpliciter is not evaluated as an ad
hominem argument or an ad hominem
fallacy.
Informal
Guide to Ad Hominem Fallacy
Person L proffers claim p.
Person L's circumstances or character
is unsatisfactory or L does not
act in accordance with p.
Claim p is implausible or unlikely.
- The Ad hominem abusive is the fallacy that
that an agent's belief has not been proved (or is mistaken) because
that person is somehow deficient as evidenced by some undesirable
aspects of that person's character, personality, morality, or
competence. Consider
this example:
“After a 35-year career in agriculture, which took me to all
corners of the world in segments ranging from animal productivity to
plant protection, genetics, and biotechnology, I … reviewed
Prince Charles' speech. I found foolishness and arrogant condescension.”
Rather than commenting on the content of Prince Charles' speech, the
author attempts to discredit Prince Charles by stating his writing
exhibits foolishness and arrogant condescension.
- The Ad hominem circumstantial is the fallacy
that someone's belief has not been proved (or is mistaken) because that
person's position is motivated by actions or personal circumstances which
most likely bias that person's judgment. This is a fairly typical example:
“[Alger] Hiss still has a ragtag remnant of defenders, historical
illiterates who are disproportionately academics. They often are the last
to learn things because they have gone to earth in the groves of academe in
order to live in an alternative reality.
Rather than demonstrating mistakes made by defenders of Alger Hiss,
the writer shifts from that issue to a claim that most of the
defenders of such a view are situated as historically illiterate
academics who seclude themselves from the everyday world.
- Since the circumstantial variety of the ad hominem
fallacy can often be regarded as a special case of the abusive in that
it is an indirect personal attack, the distinction between the ad
hominem abusive and the ad hominem circumstantial is
in some contexts an inconsequential distinction. For example, consider the
following argument wherein a politician defends objections to his bill
before a municipal committee:
“Mr. Chairman and Gentlemen of the Committee: I am the
father of this bill, and I have listened with a great deal of
attention to all that has been said against it. … The
gentleman who last spoke has too good a reputation as a lawyer
in Hudson County to lead me to believe that he believes what
he has just stated.”
The lawyer's circumstances are used to establish his character in
an effort to deprecate his objections to the bill. Notice, as well,
that the appeal to character in an ad hominem fallacy
need not always be abusive.
-
An ad hominem argument can be a response to any multi-person
advocate or agent, not just an individual. Consider this argument
in defense of the U.S. Emergency Tariff Act of 1921:
”The Democrats have no right to attack a Republican protective
tariff measure on the ground that it would increase the cost of living,
for … [u]nder a recent Democratic administration the living cost
was higher than at any other time during the history of the
country.”
This argument is fallacious in that does not endeavor to prove the
Democrats are mistaken in their claim that a protective tariff would
increase the cost of living; instead, the argument diverts attention
from consideration of the tariff to a previous failing of a Democrats.
(The version of ad hominem in this argument is the
tu quoque fallacy discussed below.)
- Occasionally, in the literature, the definition of argumentum
ad hominem includes arguments that someone's belief is true or probable
because that person's character or circumstances is eminent, authoritative or
trustworthy. Such virtue
argumentation or positive ethotic arguments are relevant in the evaluation of
evidence in witness testimony.
- Christopher Johnson points out:
[T]he stronger or more coherent the character portrait that develops
from consideration of these virtues and traits, the more compelling
the ad hominem appeal, and the less the objection of
ad hominem fallacy, in making a decision between
arguments.”
Honest persons are likely to speak truthfully.
- Indeed, often such arguments as these are non-fallacious since the
premises of a reliable source of information provides evidence for the
truth of conclusion.
- Many textbook accounts of ad hominem arguments assume
all instances are mistakes in reasoning since the evaluation of arguments
depends on the nature or the argument rather than the character of the arguer.
On this view, the argument, itself, is to be evaluated, not the individual
adducing the argument. However, an ad hominem argument can be
transposed as Merilee Salmon has proposed into a (formal) inductive
argument :
Most of what person L states about subject S
is true.
Person L states claim c on subject
S.
Claim c is probably true.
Christian Dahlman, et al. have proposed an intriguing formal approach to
the ad hominem arguments which provides a more consistent and
thorough description its subtypes. They propose reconstruction of ad
hominem arguments as deductively valid arguments with a false premise and
then classify the kind of arguments in terms of the kind of false
premise.
This approach works well as a principle of organization, but neglects
the character of informal arguments as providing degrees of support and
different standards of evidence rather than limiting informal logic to
appraisal in terms of deductive inferences.
- Informal logic is characterized by its lack of formal structure and can be
viewed as an activity of discourse where an arguer's character or circumstances
lend credibility to that individual's claims. So, on this point of view, informal
logic is concerned with pragmatic analysis of dialectical interaction in discourse
rather than the textual analysis of the logic of statements as is realized in
deductive logic.
Argumentative discourse, oral or written, is meant to resolve a difference of
opinion, but when an ad hominem fallacy is used as a tactic to
disqualify an opponent's arguments, the discussion is derailed.
FIG. 1. Historical Frequency of Use of
“ad hominem” and “argumentum
ad hominem” in Google Books 1775-2008
The Question of Relevance in Ad
Hominem Arguments
Argumentum ad Hominem: reasoning by
appealing to the character or circumstances of an individual who is
advancing a claim in order to determine the plausibility of that claim.
The argumentum ad hominem is not always fallacious; an
individual's personal character and circumstances are sometimes logically
related to the issues under discussion. As Douglas Walton notes,
“Evaluation of each individual case should be made in
relation to the corpus of argument and the context of
dialogue.”
- The informal fallacy of argumentum ad hominem occurs
when an examination of issues is discontinued in pursuance of
an irrelevant personal attack against the advocate of the issues —
e.g., impeaching the testimony of a reliable eye witness to a
felony.
- When an examination of issues is logically benefited by
reference to the character or circumstances of an individual,
no informal fallacy occurs — such as impeaching the
testimony of a visually impaired eye witness to a felony.
- Note that for the argumentum ad hominem fallacy
to occur, (1) an irrelevant appeal is fabricated and (2) a logical
argument must have been
submitted.
- The commonsensical assumptions upon which the argumentum
ad hominem is based generally include (1) the belief that flawed
persons are not credible or logical or, as well, in a different case,
(2) the belief that decent persons are trustworthy and reasonable.
Aristotle points out that in matters of uncertainty, the speaker's
character can be relevant to the given argument:
“Persuasion is achieved by the speaker's personal
character when the speech is so spoken as to make us think him credible.
… [T]his is … absolutely true where exact certainty is
impossible and opinions are divided.” Rh. 1.2.1356a
(trans. Roberts)
Obviously, however, the fact that an argument is given by a person of
good character does not guarantee the truth of the conclusion.
- The fallacy version of ad hominem draws
its appeal from the technique of “getting personal.” But
the fallacy does not occur when unfavorable evidence adduced for the
accused proponent is logically dependent on the argument being put forward
by the proponent.
- If the grounds for the claim about character or circumstances are
logically independent of the antagonist's argument itself, then the claim,
not being relevant, can be to be assessed in accordance with other (relevant)
reasons. But that would be to miss the point.
- But, with regard to monotonic reasoning, as James Cargile writes,
“[E]vidence that the source of a claim is likely to be wrong is not
evidence against the claim. The tendency to overlook this is the essential
feature of the ad hominem fallacy.
- Unfortunately, a criterion of relevance (or for that matter, a criterion
of irrelevance) associating the circumstances and character of an arguer to
the arguer's argument is extraordinarily difficult to establish for all types
of ad hominem arguments.
- What is relevant to a particular argument depends upon the context
within which the argument is proposed. Currently, difficult cases are
hashed out in reasoned dialogue, although, it must be admitted, the
fallaciousness of many individual occurrences of argumentum ad
hominem is in dispute in the current informal fallacy literature.
- The defeasibility
close ×
Defeasible Reasoning
Nondeductive reasoning wherein supportive evidence for a conclusion is
given, and it is possible that the argument can be defeated by additional
evidence. Hence, the premises of the argument could be true and the conclusion
false. Defeasible reasoning includes inductive, abductive and analogical
reasoning. of ad hominem arguments is
shown by the presence of other factors in some arguments which render exception
to the charge of fallacious reasoning. In many textbooks, relevance in informal
logic is taken to be undefined: a primitive term or an intuitive notion.
- Simply criticizing an adversary as a digression from a controversy is not
necessarily an ad hominem fallacy unless the personal attack
is intended to dismiss the arguments which are unrelated to the adversary's
character.
Stephen Toulmin states, ”[R]elevance is a substantive matter, to be
discussed in science by scientists, in law by lawyers, and so on. There
are very few ‘conditions of relevance’ of an entirely general
kind that hold good in all fields and forums and apply to apply types of
arguments.”
Some Varieties of Ad Hominem: Ad
Personam, Ad Feminam, Tu Quoque, Two Wrongs Fallacy,
Ex Concessis, and Ex Aliquem
Although there is no generally accepted consensus, many logicians today
distinguish several prevailing indistinct varieties of fallacies related
to the argumentum ad hominem fallacy.
- In the ad personam
fallacy the statement or argument at issue is dropped from consideration
or is completely ignored, and the adversary's character or circumstances is
subjected to personal attack.
FIG. 2. Historical Frequency of Use of
“argumentum ad hominem” and
“argumentum ad personam” in Google Books
1700-2008
Recently in several logic sources, the ad personam is
taken to be a name replacement for the traditional ad
hominem because ad hominem, which means
“‘to’ or ‘toward’ a human
being (or the person),” might be misinterpreted if the
Latin phrase is translated to mean “‘to’ or
‘toward’ the man.”
- This latter translation may well be part of
the reason some recent writers have added the separate fallacy of
ad feminam to their list of informal
fallacies, a
fallacy sometimes defined as an attack on a woman's character or
circumstances in order to cast doubt on her claims.
- Consider this example of an ad personam (which
can also be classified as either an ad hominem abusive
fallacy or a name calling fallacy):
“Secretary of State John Kerry says that there is less violence
than usual in the world right now. Meanwhile the Director of National
Intelligence, James Clapper, says the opposite, that terrorism is more
violent and dangerous than ever. Since Clapper is Director of National
Intelligence, maybe Kerry should have the title Director of National
Stupidity.“
- A well known ad personam example of the ad
hominem (circumstantial) variety is Voltaire's criticism of Rousseau's
Emile, or Treatise on Education by reason of Rousseau's dereliction
of his own children:
“Excessive pride and envy have destroyed
Jean-Jacques, my illustrious philosopher. That
monster dares speak of education! He abandoned
his children and the tramp with whom he made
them.”
Voltaire dismisses Rousseau's theory of education on account of Rousseau's
hypocrisy in sending his children, on the occasion of their birth, to the
Paris Foundling Hospital.
- Unfortunately, the ad personam fallacy has not been
consistently used and defined from an historical point of view. The
ad personam is often defined as an abandonment of the
object of argument for an appeal to personal interest
or the interest of interested observers.
- Schopenhauer designates our contemporary sense of the “ad
hominem” abusive informal fallacy, where the object of a dispute is
cast aside and its proponent is attacked, an “ad personam.” And James H. Hyslop defines
the ad personam as any argument not directed correctly to the
issue (i.e., it's not an argumentum ad rem, an argument
directed to the point in dispute). Thus, Hyslop defines the ad
personam as including these five types of traditional fallacies: the
ad judicium, ad populum, ad hominem,
ad verecundiam, and ad ignorantiam.
- The tu quoque fallacy, where the
proponent responds to an ad hominem attack with
the same accusation against the person to whom
the proponent is confronting, is a narrower form of the
ad hominem circumstantial fallacy. In other words,
rather than trying to disprove an accuser's proposed argument
against one's own position, one responds by asserting
that the same kind of argument applies to the accuser.
The inconsistency of a claimant is shown by accusing the
claimant of the same sort of allegation for which a proponent
has been denounced. Consequently, what the accuser accuser
does and what the accuser says are shown to be at variance.
Informal Guide to Tu Quoque
Person L proffers negative claim y
against person M.
Person M retorts the same negative claim y
applies against person L.
Person M is exonerated.
Whenever the response in kind to an advocates' claim or argument does not
involve a personal attack either of character or circumstances, the tu
quoque fallacy would not be considered a type of ad hominem
fallacy.
FIG. 3. Historical Frequency of Use of “argumentum ad
hominem” and “tu quoque” in Google Books 1700-2008
- In cross examination or in debate, the tu quoque fallacy is
sometimes depicted as “My argument might be bad, but yours is
worse.” Thus, the conversational implication is my argument is good
by way of comparison. Note that this fallacy is usually only rhetorically
effective in the presence of a third party.
- If the basis of dispute is the criticism of a someone's argument, the
fallacy can be summarized as “O.K., I understand your criticism of
my contention, but the same criticism you point out applies to your thinking
as well.” As Aristotle wrote, “[F]or it is the absurdity of
impudence to arraign others for the very same things of which we ourselves
have been guilty,”
and again, “The second way is, when a defender discredits his accuser,
by retorting his own accusations.”
- By way of example of the fallacy of tu quoque, consider
this anecdote told by an early feminist social reformer:
“In the discussion after a Forum lecture in Boston, an address on
some aspect of the Woman question, a man in the gallery, who evidently took
exception to a dull rose fillet I wore in my hair, demanded to know how women
could expect to equal men ‘so long as they took so much time fixing up
their hair and putting ribbons in it’? There was some commotion, and
cries of ‘Put him out!’ but I grinned up at him cheerfully and
replied, ‘I do not think it has been yet established whether it takes a
woman longer to do her hair than it does a man to shave.’ This was not
an answer at all, but it seemed to please every one but the
inquirer.”
Notice how the lecturer recognizes the irrelevancy of her response to the audience
member's impertinent remark.
- The imputation of tu quoque can be defended by pointing out essential
differences between the accusation of the arguer and the accusation of the critic.
However, the supposed difference of transgressions can only be determined individually
by sorting out the transgressions.
- A fallacy closely related to tu quoque is the fallacy of
two wrongs make a right — in fact, some logic texts equate the two
fallacies. The two wrongs-fallacy attempts to rationalize the rightness of a wrong
action on the basis that the action is merely a justified response to a previous
occurring wrong action of another or of a similar kind.
- Since the relationships among the ad hominem
circumstantial, the tu quoque and the two wrongs
fallacy are classified differently in the current logic
literature, it's perhaps prudent not to insist upon
distinct definitions.
- Usually, however, in the two wrongs fallacy, the
first wrong is not taken as an ad hominem
recrimination, whereas in the tu quoque fallacy,
the initial wrong is taken as an ad hominem
attack.
- A fairly typical example of the two-wrongs fallacy
is that reported of a London music dealer who was brought
before the London Magistrates' Court charged with pirating
music:
“His excuse, such as it was, had not even the
merit of novelty, although he pleaded that he sold
pirated music on principle and not for profit! He said
that there was a music right in London, which certainly
paid royalties to authors who could command their prices,
but they said nothing of the small authors, whom they
bled for all they were worth. The charge for music was
extortionate and exorbitant, but he had no wish to rob
an author, who had a right to the value of his
work.
The music dealer pleaded that since the publisher paid
composers so meagerly and sold the music so substantially,
he was justified in freebooting. The magistrate noted the
two-wrongs fallacy that robbing a music publisher does not
benefit the author of the music and so ruled guilty and
imposed a fine.
- The argumentum ex concessis
is, generally speaking, an argument composed only from declarations or
admissions by an opponent (and not from statements generally considered
acceptable). The several varieties of ex consessis include comparison
of the opponent's concession with another statement either by the opponent
or by the proponent of the argument and is not always fallacious.
Informal Guide to Ex
Concessis
Person L proffers claim c.
Person L previously held view d
inconsistent with claim c
Claims c and d cannot both be true.
Historically, the wide adoption of the ex concessis as a method
of argumentation based on an opponent's own premises was anticipated by
Aristotle:
Moreover, as in rhetorical arguments, so likewise also in refutations,
you ought to look for contradictions between the answerer's views
and either his own statements or the views of those whose words and
actions he admits to be right, or of those who are generally held
to bear a like character and to resemble them, or of the majority or
of all mankind.
The fallacy occurs whenever an opponent is charged with taking a position
or acting in such a manner (in which case ex consessis converges
with ad hominem circumstantial) inconsistent with, or
conflicting with, a previous position the opponent accepted. The fallacy is
usually based on the comparison of two conflicting positions of the opponent.
The charge of mistaken reasoning is supported by any resulting logical
inconsistency.
In Biblical scholarship, for example, the use of argumentum
ex concessis is used to evaluate consistency between the Old and
New Testaments.
- Here's a typical example of the ad hominem ex concessis
fallacy:
“[An] octogenarian professor from the University of Texas named
Lino Graglia … dutifully informed the committee that ‘a
law ending birthright citizenship should and likely would survive
constitutional challenge.’ But consider the source: [he is] a man
who by his own account takes ‘a very limited view of the power
of the Supreme Court‘ and breezily dismisses contrary
precedents.”
As noted above, this particular type of ex concessis may also
be appraised as an ad hominem circumstantial argument.
Also, note that the argument does not prove anything with respect to
the object of the dispute (i.e., ending birthright citizenship);
the argument only points to the opponent's purported inconsistency.
- Nevertheless, in many of the first historical uses of the argument,
the argumentum ex concessis is composed upon the
statements of the opponent, whether they be true or false: the
argument is designated an ad hominem or “personal
argument” and is not necessarily fallacious. Revealing an
inconsistency in an opponent's claims in a dialectical exchange is, of
course, in itself, a legitimate argument.
For example in 1689, John Locke characterizes a way of reasoning in order
“to press a man with consequences drawn from his own principles,
or concessions.” Locke describes this kind of reasoning as a type of
argument rather than as a type of fallacy.
In the early 1700's Isaac Watts describes (without naming)
argumentum ex concessis:
“When it [i.e. an argument] is built upon the profest
[i.e., professed] Principles or Opinions of the Person with whom
we argue, whether these Opinions be true or false, it is named
Argumentum ad Hominem, an Address to our profest
Principles.”
In 1826, Richard Whately defines the argumentum ad hominem
in terms of ex concessis and only as a fallacy when
“unfairly used” as a “personal argument” rather than
an “argumentum ad rem.” Yet, it can be allowed,
he says, “in order to silence those who will not yield to fair general
argument” and can be allowed in “shifting the burden of proof.”
Whately further points out:
“[T]he conclusion which actually is established, is not the absolute
and general one in question, but relative and particular; … that
‘this man is bound to admit it, in conformity to his principles
of Reasoning, or in consistency with his own conduct, situation,’
&c.”
He adds that such an argument will often justly shift the burden of proof
to the opponent.
- This form of the argumentum ex concessis occurs when
someone is accused of being hypocritical and is personally accused of not
believing in, or not acting in accordance with, commitments he has taken
on another occasion.
For example, in his “An Essay on Miracles”
David Hume points the inconsistency in the everyday believer by describing
supposed miraculous events he presumes no person would presently accept and
then submits that it is so likewise reasonable to conclude such incredulous
events would not have occurred in the past either.
- Interestingly, in the 1850's, William and Robert Chambers argued that
this variety of argumentum ad hominem can be viewed as
nonfallacious in cases where the conclusion is the legitimate exception to
a rule. E.g., a foundational “commitment” is expressed
in the book of Exodus, where God says to Moses:
“Ye shall keep the sabbath therefore: for it is holy unto
you: every one that defileth it shall surely be put to death: for
whosoever doeth any work therein, that soul shall be cut off from
among his people.”
Yet, in the Gospel of Luke, Jesus justifies to a group of Pharisees (religious
leaders who based Judaism in part on the Laws of Moses) his task of healing on
the Sabbath as follows as an exception to the law:
“2 And, behold there was a certain man before
him which had the dropsy.
3 And Jesus answering spake unto the lawyers and
Pharisees, saying, Is it lawful to heal on the sabbath day?
4 And they held their peace. And he took him,
and healed him, and let him go;
5 And answered them, saying, Which of you shall have
an ass or an ox fallen into a pit, and will not straightaway pull him out
on the sabbath day?
6 And they could not answer him again to these
things.”
Thus, in suggesting the practice of healing does not violate the
precept of the Pharisees that work defiles the Sabbath, the practice
is seen as being in accordance with their beliefs. The practice
is seen as acceptable to the Pharisees, but not proved to be
acceptable in itself.
- So, in this use of ex concessis argumentum ad
hominem, Moses Stuart points out in 1829, “[W]hat is called
the argumentum ad hominem or the argumentum
ex concessis … the argument is not conclusive in itself,
its conclusiveness would be admitted by those who admitted what is
implied in the premises.”
- Obviously, a simple inconsistency in thought or action is not a
fallacy unless the inconsistency is part of the same argument under
consideration. The ex concessis variety of the
ad hominem fallacy occurs when the previous commitment
or position is not specifically germane to the specific subject under
consideration.
- The ex concessis form of the fallacy is committed
when an interlocutor states that his opponent's argument must
be mistaken because his opponent has previously given an argument
or taken a position which is inconsistent with the present argument
or position. But the fact that the opponent might, at one time,
have believed something different from what the present argument
provides, does not necessarily imply the present argument or
claim is mistaken as a matter of fact.
- Schopenhauer clarifies another variant of this form of fallacious
reasoning: “Should your opponent be in the right, but luckily
for your contention, choose a faulty proof, you can easily manage to
refute it, and then claim you have refuted his whole position. This
trick … is, at bottom, an expedient by which an
argumentum ad hominem is put forward …
”
- Another traditional type of ad hominem which can
be considered as ex concessis occurs in the course
of convincing an opponent when the proponent's view can be shown to be
a conclusion of an opponent's prejudices or questionable beliefs.
- Obviously, even if the opponent concedes the view, the view has
not been proved to be the case. In this form ex concessis,
the argument is directed to the opponent, but the opponent is not
being attacked.
- For example, W.E. Taylor notes Bishop Joseph Butler's analogies are
an “argumentum ad hominem in defense of miracles
and Biblical inconsistencies as they “show indeed that his own
conclusions are capable of valid proofs even on the principles laid down
by his [naturalistic] opponents.”
Fallacies Related to ad Hominem:
Personal, Attack, Name Calling, Poisoning the Well, Guilt by Association,
Genetic Fallacy
Other fallacies associated with, or overlapping with, the main types of
ad hominem outlined above include the personal attack,
name calling, and poisoning the well, guilt (or honor) by
association, and the genetic fallacy.
- The personal attack fallacy is often regarded
as a harsh ad hominem abusive fallacy, but it can also
occur as an ad hominem circumstantial fallacy. Note the
disproportionate criticism in the following example:
“We hold that the deceitful and vacuous writings presented by
Lyotard, and by many of his fellow postmodernists, are texts that
purposely lead their readers to stray into errancy. … Often,
they reject all and any truth, and merely spread ignorance and mendacity.
Hence, these deceitful vacuous writings belong in the dustbin of
history!”
The personal attack is based on what the locutor is accused of doing;
name calling is based on who the person is accused of being.
- The fallacy of name calling,
also often a variant of the ad hominem abusive fallacy, occurs
on those occasions where loaded or negatively-slanted epithets or appellations
characterizing a speaker are used to cast doubt on the worth of the speaker's
beliefs. Often such insults are used to devalue the opposition's arguments or
beliefs.
- For the name-calling fallacy to occur, the critic must have used
irrelevant name calling as a reason for doubting the advocate's argument
or conclusion. Thus, any evidence of the name's propriety is not
necessarily evidence against the argument or conclusion itself.
- The following point of view is a typical example of name calling:
“Justice Antonin Scalia was right. Not about gay marriage,
of course. Scalia is so antediluvian he has trouble forcing
himself to call it by its proper
name.”
The ad hominem fallacy occurs here since the writer
asserts that the reason Supreme Court Justice Scalia does not use the
proper term for same sex marriage is that the Justice is antediluvian.
- Note that simply using abusive names to belittle a person is not
fallacious in itself. Occasionally name calling is done in order to
divert attention away from the argument under discussion. The following
passage seems fallacious, but it is an instance of nonargumentative
name calling. Lexically, the example can be properly termed an
ad hominem, but, logically, not an ad
hominem fallacy.
“Politicians and lawyers pretend they are important people doing
important work, but often they're important because they are parasites.
They feed off others, while creating no wealth of their own.
This type of character attack is based on the slanted language of emotive
significance rather than based on a logical mistake.
- The fallacy of poisoning the well is,
in a sense, a kind of preemptive ad hominem argument. In
poisoning the well, a disputant claims that an adversary's arguments cannot
be trusted to be credible because of an adversary's prior fixed opinion or
previous commitment. Such a person is said to be untrustworthy in present
assertions because, it is claimed, that person has always been prejudiced and
narrow-minded. In nearly all poisoning-the-well examples a person's motives
are used to attempt to discredit the claims of that person and so are
instances of the ad hominem circumstantial fallacy.
Poisoning the Well
Informal Guide
Person L proclaims person M has
an objectionable standpoint or associations.
Person M's claims are implausible or unlikely.
- Since we normally assess the truth of a claim by a body of existing
beliefs, if the existing belief-set is suspect, then our ability to
assess the claim is seriously undermined. So in the fallacy of poisoning
the well, odious information about an adversary is preemptively adduced
in order to discredit any possible response made by the opponent.
The fallacy is illustrated in the following example where a conservative
British politician's assessment of the European Union referendum and
Brexit are thwarted by this criticism:
“The poisonous rancour of Norman Tebbit is nothing new, but even
their lordships gasped at his complaint about ‘looking after
foreigners and not the British.’”
- E.g., consider the following example of accusing an opponent of
the kind of fixed bias implicit in poisoning the well:
“Michael closed his eyes as if to shut out the world
around him. ‘You'll never understand what it means to swear allegiance
to the flag and to your country. You'll never understand what it means to
be a soldier.’
[Samantha] ‘You're right, Michael, I don't understand,
and I will never understand why men have to kill each other. It is beyond
my comprehension why you had to fight in this useless war. A war that is so
wrong and should have never happened.’”
Michael's argument here is that since Samantha cannot understand
what it means to be a soldier, she cannot understand the values
of a soldier.
- In gender studies, for example, poisoning the well occurs
when it is sometimes assumed that women and men will never
understand each other's point of view because of their inherent
differences. From the outset, this assumption forestalls the
possibility of a common neutral understanding and sets up an
irremediable barrier to meaningful interactive discourse. When
examined, such a presupposition would imply that no one could
ever understand anything inherently different from one's own
point of view. Ultimately, examples such as this one are fraught
with difficulties similar to the intractable
problem of other minds. For this reason, these types of poisoning
the well can be rhetorically defended via a tu quoque
maneuver:
Mary: Your views on limited government can have no possible
standing because you're a Republican, and it's a view all Republicans
are necessarily possessed by.
John: Well, of course, you cannot understand the need for
a limited government since that wouldn't support your own interests
as a Democrat.
I.e., John returns the same kind of biased-based poisoning-the-well
disqualification to Mary.
- The fallacy of guilt by association, a fallacy
resembling in some ways poisoning the well, often makes use of ad
hominem considerations. In the fallacy of guilt by association, the
contentions or arguments of a proponent are judged on the basis of the
proponent's discredited or suspicious affiliations. Thus, the adversary's
position is attacked on the grounds that the adversary belongs to some kind
of questionable or suspect social group. The allegation is as follows: because
the advocate is somehow affiliated with a discredited enterprise, the agent's
claims are not credible.
The positive analogue of this fallacy is honor by association
where an advocate is connected to an esteemed group and is thereby
considered credible. The fallacy of honor by association is one aspect
of the cognitive bias first named by Edward Thorndike as the halo
effect. Psychologically, a person is often judged in accordance with
judgments about associated persons, but this judgment only carries
logical import when that association is relevant to the issue at hand.
Informal Guide to Guilt (or
Honor) By Association
Person L proffers claim c.
Person L has qualities in common with disreputable
(or reputable, if by honor) group G.
Person L's character is disreputable (or reputable,
if by honor) or claim c is implausible (or plausible, if
by honor).
- Many instances of this fallacy are instances of what Stuart
Chase has termed “guilt-by-verbal-association,” and
not physical association. These examples are clearly imparted
as examples of the syllogistic formal fallacy of the undistributed middle term. Chase
formalizes an example which was used by the real estate lobby
during the McCarthy era in the U.S.:
Communists are in favor of government housing.
Sen. Taft is in favor of government housing.
Therefore Sen. Taft is a Communist.
As Chase points out, “It is the standard bludgeon of what
we now call ‘McCarthyism.”
- And here's a more recent example of what might be called
guilt by physical association:
“[Rep. Michele] Bachmann has raised questions about
Huma Abedin, a Muslim-American, who is deputy chief of
staff to Secretary of State Hillary Clinton. Bachmann's
concern is Abedin's relatives in the Middle East some of
whom — such as Abedin's mother — she claims
‘are connected to Muslim Brotherhood operatives and/or
organizations.’ Abedin's job, according to Bachmann,
‘affords her routine access to the secretary and to
policy making.’ And, as a result of that access, says
Bachmann, ‘the State Department, and in several cases,
the specific direction of the secretary of state, have taken
actions recently that have been enormously favorable to the
Muslim Brotherhood and its interests.’”
Adducing circumstantial evidence in this fashion of “raising
doubts” is also a common tactic in one form of an ignoratio elenchi fallacy.
- The genetic fallacy can
converge with the ad hominem circumstantial and abusive
fallacies, but not all variations involve personal attacks. (C.f.,
for example, the explanation of the causal genetic fallacy.)
The genetic fallacy is an irrelevant attempt to refute or establish a claim
or argument on the basis of its origin or history. The mistake in reasoning
occurs because the historical temporal or causal origins of a viewpoint
is confused with its logical or justifiable merit.
In other words, the discourse of a historical account of how something came
to be is different from the discourse of an analytical account of that thing.
Some logicians maintain that ad hominem arguments are directed
at a single person or a persons of a certain category whereas genetic arguments
involve only circumstantial or ideational sources — other logicians do
not make this distinction.
Informal Structure of
Genetic Fallacy
Standpoint or circumstance x is the historical
source of conception or claim y.
Standpoint or circumstance x is unsatisfactory
in some way.
[Standpoint or circumstance x or its aspects
are irrelevant to understanding the conception or claim y.]
Conception or claim y is unlikely.
The source of how evidence is obtained is often irrelevant to logical
significance of the evidence. I.e., the logical correctness of an
argument is usually independent of the source or historical origin of that
argument. The correctness of a conception should be judged on its own basis
rather than judged on the basis of its sources or adherents.
- If the origin of an argumentative claim arises from an agent or
person of some kind, the cogency of that claim or belief is not justified
when the source is not logically related to the claim. A claim is to be
justified on the basis of its own merit.
- Here's a brief allusion to a fallacy which can be properly
reconstructed as an ad hominem fallacy or a genetic
fallacy:
“Would one regard a theorem in mathematics less praiseworthy
because its discoverer was uneducated, or otherwise disreputably
credentialed?”
- James William Lett provides two interesting examples of this type of
genetic fallacy:
“Alfred Russell Wallace reportedly conceived the
principle of natural selection while in a delirium; to
dismiss the theory of evolution of that basis would be
to commit the genetic fallacy. Postmodernists who reject
scientific claims to knowledge on the grounds that those
claims emerged from the hegemonic discourse of a powerful
elite are likewise guilty of the genetic
fallacy.”
Note the overlap in Lett's postmodernist example of the genetics fallacy
with the fallacy of poisoning the well.
- A second type of genetic fallacy occurs often in the sciences where an
entity, state, or activity is reduced to, or identified with, the phenomena
or physical processes which occasion it.
- E.g., William R. Klemm appears to commit this
fallacy when he writes:
“[C]onsciousness is constituted by neural events and
does not have to intervene in neural processes because
consciousness is a neural
process.”
Simply because consciousness arises from neural events, it does not
necessarily follow that consciousness, itself, is the same thing as a series
of neural events.
- The mind-brain identity theory is often challenged on the same basis:
“The classic mind-brain identity theory, according
to which pain is necessarily C-fiber stimulation, does not
allow for pain to be anything other than C-fiber
stimulation.”
The basis for the charge of mistaken reasoning is the claim that since pain
originates in C-fiber stimulation, pain is nothing but C-fiber stimulation.
- A third type of genetic fallacy is the presumption that a descriptive
historical account of the origin of biological, psychological or ethical aspects
of organisms is always sufficient for a logical understanding or a normative
justification.
E.g., Peter Godfrey-Smith points to the tenuousness of Thomas Nagel's
suggestion that the use of reason should be justifiable on the basis of its
biological origin:
“Nagel does not merely ask for an explanation of how our powers of
reasoning come to exist, and how they came to work as well as they do, but
also asks that the evolutionary story give us ‘grounds for trusting’
them. This is a demand, though, that no evolutionary account needs to
meet.
- A fourth form of the genetic fallacy is based upon a distinction made by
Hans Reichenbach which “springs from a confusion of context of
discovery and context of justification.”
“The act of discovery escapes logical analysis; there are no logical
rules in terms of which a ‘discovery machine’ could be constructed
that would take over the creative function of the genius. But it is not the
logician's task to account for scientific discoveries; all he can do is to
analyze the relation between given facts and a theory presented to him with
the claim that it explains these facts. In other words, logic is concerned
only with the context of justification.”
Karl Popper states:
“The question how it happens that a new idea occurs to a man
… may be of great interest to empirical psychology; but it is
irrelevant to the logical analysis of scientific knowledge. This latter
is concerned not with question of fact … but on with
questions of justification or validity.”
The context of discovery is examined through descriptive and
explicative methods of empirical inquiry, whereas the context of
justification is the logical analysis of the resultant outcomes
of discovery.
- Reichenbach and Popper, notwithstanding, in some arguments
factors in the context of discovery are relevant to the import
of the conclusion. Often discoveries are made solely by logical
reasoning in mathematics and the theoretical sciences. As well,
justification in various modes of inquiry often evolves as
addition data is adduced. Falsification by means of further
discovery can alter theoretical conclusions.
In such cases, a premise stating a relationship between discovery
and theory can be correctly part of the context of justification.
Obviously, such genetic arguments as these require valuation on a
case-by-case basis.
- E.g., the evolutionary and historical origins of some
psychological, religious, political, or ethical metaphysical
doctrines can be rendered less likely since they are satisfactorily
accounted for on empirical principles and the principle of
simplicity. This includes using the historical origins of fields
of inquiry such as the varieties of conflicting religious beliefs,
and interpretation of doctrines; altered states of consciousness
and mystical, out-of-body, and deja vu experiences; varieties
of conflicting political systems; as well as biological origins of
some ethical and epistemological intuition.
- Richard Kitchener considers a number of arguments against the
genesis–justification distinction, as well as insights against the
kinds of genetic arguments raised above:
(1) the fact–norm distinction,
(2) the discovery–justification distinction,
(3) the conceptual–empirical distinction, and,
following Quine,
(4) the analytic–synthetic distinction.
His arguments indirectly indicate that a genetic epistemology
is possible; hence, Kitchener effectively shows the possibility
of the relevance of discovery or genesis of an idea to
its justification.
Consequently, with genetic arguments, the question of relevance
is crucial in assessing the inferential legitimacy of the
argument.
- In the following definitions from Dagobert Runes'
Dictionary of Philosophy, Ledger Wood limits the
application of the genetic fallacy to instances where the
original source is deprecated:
“Genetic Fallacy: The
misapplication of the genetic method resulting in the
depreciatory appraisal of the product of a historical or
evolutionary process because of its lowly origin.
Genetic Method: Explanation of things
in terms of their origin or genesis.”
The definition of the genetic fallacy, however, is inaccurate
since the definition of “fallacy” is broadened here
to include an error of explanation involving negative emotive
significance, whereas in logical inquiry, the term
“fallacy” is usually defined in terms of a mistake
in reasoning in arguments. I.e., the mistakes in
reasoning are not that the explanation is in error and that
the appraisal is negative (or positive). The mistake of the
genetic fallacy is in the denial of the truth of an issue on
the basis of the irrelevancy of its historical origins.
- Not all genetic accounts are defective arguments, and many
are controversial. In some cases cognizance of the origins of a
viewpoint or conclusion is in fact an inference to the best
explanation in inductive argumentation. An evolutionary account
of the development of the origin of religious or logical thinking
is not always an irrelevant consideration in assessing its
trustworthiness even though such an account is not deductively
certain.
- Kim Sterelny concludes: “[T]he so-called
‘genetic fallacy’ (the erroneous supposition
that a defect in the genesis of something is evidence that
discredits the thing itself) need be no fallacy. A causal
account of the origins and maintenance of belief can
undermine that belief's rational
warrant.”
- The structure or correctness of a conception or
argument is not necessarily logically independent of the
prevailing conditions under which it came to be discovered.
Sometimes the understanding of a conception is constitutively
reliant on the circumstances of its discovery and development.
Thus, a historically descriptive account of how a judgment
commences is sometimes essentially relevant to the
epistemological status of that judgment. In general, if the
argument involves a justification for a person's belief,
then how that person arrived at that belief can be relevant.
However, if the argument is about the truth of the belief,
then how that person arrived at that belief is unlikely
to be relevant.
Evaluating Ad Hominem
Arguments for Relevance
Several considerations for evaluating ad hominem passages
deserve comment:
- In the examination of scientific, literary or philosophical works,
looking at the author's character or circumstance can sometimes
provide insight into that individual's standpoint. In other words,
ad hominem considerations can show motives and can
sometimes provide a frame of reference for deeper comprehension.
However, these perspectives do not ordinarily demonstrate the truth
or falsity of the ideas. Consider the following passage:
“John Stacy … made the connection between the radical
power of Byron's poetics and his Satanic as well as melancholic genius.
Accusing Byron of a ‘misanthropy run mad,’ of trying
‘to make the world believe he is miserable, and to persuade it
to be as miserable as himself’, the author writes ‘I grant
him genius …, an eloquence of poetry …’”
The suggestion that the brilliance of Lord Byron's poetry
might be due to his manic-depressive illness is a literary
insight into the possible literary effect of specific
characteristics of Byron's personality. No fallacy occurs here
because no argument is present.
- The character of a person is often relevant for an evaluation
of the sincerity of views being offered and so can be relevant for
pragmatic decision-making.
E.g., D. M. Varisco explains the necessity of having awareness
of Edward Said's circumstances in order to make sense of Said's
1978 polemical book Orientalism objecting to the
presumption of Western superiority in its patronizing description
of the Eastern World:
“From the start the reactions to Orientalism,
ranging from the ad hoc to the ad
hominem, read into Said the critic as well and as poorly as
into what the critic was saying. Said's origins and political
activism as an Arab-American intellectual can hardly be left out of
analysis.”
The claim, here, is that understanding Edward Said's writing requires
knowledge of Edward Said's past circumstances.
- A fallacy might occur in passages such as these if the work were to be
considered misguided and discredited solely because of the degenerate character
and circumstances of the author. The essential question in judging whether or
not an ad hominem argument is a fallacy is whether or not the
author's character and circumstances are logically relevant to the assertions
or the arguments in the work itself.
Non-Fallacious Uses of Ad
Hominem Arguments
Non-fallacious uses of the ad hominem can occur in
diverse descriptive and rhetorical contexts. When evidence about
a person's character or circumstances is adduced to disclose the
motive for that person's assertion, rather than to dispute the
assertion itself, such instances often involve the presence of
a causal explanation rather than the
presence of an argument.
- In arguments where the character or circumstances
are relevant to the substance of the argument,
no fallacy occurs.
- E.g., the following passage is not fallacious:
“If [Thomas] Jefferson's relationship with [Sally]
Hemings began in the late 1780's, it would mean that he
began to back away from a leadership position in the
anti-slavery movement just around the time that his
affair with Sally Hemings started. Jefferson's stated
reservations about ending slavery included a fear that
emancipation would lead to racial mixing and
amalgamation. His own interracial affair now
personalizes this issue, while adding a dimension of
hypocrisy.”
The hypothesis is proposed that Jefferson's relationship
with Hemings abated his reservations toward the
anti-slavery movement.
- E.g., John F. Cragan and Craig W. Cutbirth argue when
Adalai Stevenson was called a wimp in the 1982 Illinois gubernatorial
Election, the ad hominem charge is relevant
to the issue of his fitness for office and so is not a fallacious
appeal. Cragan and Cutbirth rightly conclude that adducing evidence of
unfitness for office is not always a fallacy.
However, Cragan and Cutbirth mistakenly proceed to criticize a number
of logicians for proclaiming that any attempt to show a candidate's
personal unfitness for office is an ad hominem fallacy.
They cite this typical example from S. Morris Engel:
“Turning attention away from the facts in argument to the
people participating in them is characteristic not only of everyday
discussions but of many of our political debates as well. Rather
than discuss political issues soberly, rivals may find it easier to
discuss personalities and engage in mudslinging.”
Cragan and Cutbirth mistakenly conclude from this passage:
“The implication is clear. Attacking one's opponent is by
definition a fallacy.”
But this is not correct as Engel states prior to this passage that the
fallacy is “an argument that diverts attention away from the
question” — i.e., ad hominem qualifies
as a fallacy only if it is an irrelevant to some other claim being made.
- Moreover, if a speaker merely responds to an accusation pertaining to his
character or circumstances by retorting that the accuser also has the same or
similar character or circumstances, no fallacy necessarily occurs if there is
no (logical) argument present. In other words, if a disputant's rejoinder of
the same non-argumentative accusation exhibits the rhetoric of tu quoque,
it is not necessarily an instance of the tu quoque fallacy unless the
claim is implicit that the rejoinder is intended to disqualify some sort of
argumentative criticism from the accuser.
Consider this example of a non-fallacious tu quoque and simple name-calling
from the play Twelfth Night in Young England:
“BLONDEL (indignantly).—You are not one
of my century, or you would not be so discourteous. Sir, you are an
anachronism.
TELL.—Sir, you are
another.”
In this exchange, there is just an exchange of incivility:
no tu quoque fallacy is present.
- The truth or falsity of a what is said does not depend
on the character of the person saying it, unless what
is said is directly applicable to the person saying it. E.g.,
William James famously distinguishes two philosophical
temperaments:
“The history of philosophy is a clash of human
temperaments. … Of whatever temperament a
professional philosopher is, he tries, when philosophizing,
to sink the fact of his temperament. … Yet his
temperament really gives him a stronger bias than any
of his more strictly objective premises. …I
think you will practically recognize the two types of
mental make-up that I mean … by the titles
‘tender-minded’ and ‘tough-minded’
respectively.”
If James were to claim that all philosophers were either
tender-minded or tough-minded, but as a philosopher, he is not
in either camp, then the argumentum ad hominem against him
would not be deemed fallacious on account of the inconsistency
of his claims.
- Under the U.S. Federal Rules of Evidence and Case Law there
are seven proper methods of impeachment in cross-examination:
- Bias, interest, and motive
- Prior inconsistent statements
- Contradictory facts
- Prior convictions
- Character for untruthfulness
- Conduct probative of untruthfulness
- Learned Treatises (other admissible statements,
e.g. testimony of an expert
witness)
Circumstances such as these would ordinarily be relevant factors
in judging the veracity of an individual's statements.
- In brief, if the characteristics of a person constitute a
disconfirming instance of what that person claims, then an
argumentum ad hominem is not a fallacious. If the
person making a claim individually embodies a counterexample
which disproves that person's own claim, then it is not a
fallacy to point out this fact to that person. At the same time,
many ad hominem arguments provide some evidence and
in those cases cannot be considered completely irrelevant arguments.
The Ad Hominem Argument in Rhetoric
A number of logicians have argued that the argumentum ad hominem
is never a fallacy. They argue the ad hominem has been
thought fallacious since its instances do not meet the conventional logical
standards of deductive validity or inductive correctness of probability.
- On this view, in most everyday contexts of reasoning, validity or formal
inductive plausibility is thought out of place. Nevertheless, ad
hominem considerations, it is argued, do render some evidence, however
weak, and so should not be thereby presupposed to be
impertinent. This standpoint
serves to emphasize the constitutive contextual nature of informal fallacy
identifications.
- As mentioned before, when the character or circumstances of an
individual are relevant to what that person advances as a claim, the
fallacy of ad hominem does not occur. For this reason,
Douglas N. Walton has proposed re-naming the ad hominem
abusive as the ad hominem direct to reflect the
fact that the argumentum ad hominem describes both fallacious
and non-fallacious arguments.
Again, as Cummings aptly notes:
An inquiry that assumes a hierarchical structure, in which reasoning
proceeds linearly from propositions that are well known to propositions
that are less well known, is ill-equipped to accommodate the reasoning
strategies that occur in contexts of knowledge deprivation and
epistemic uncertainty.
Upon occasions of having to make a practical decision in situations of
everyday uncertainty, Alan Brinton argues for a rhetorical rather than a logical
approach to ad hominem arguments. In these situations, he states
ad hominem arguments involve a rhetorical appeal based upon the
speaker's character or personality He writes:
“[T]he most appropriate occurrences (and probably most actual
occurrences) of the ad hominem — especially in the
public sphere — are to be found in contexts which are in the appropriate
ways analogous to the contexts of classical oratory. It is most obviously
(although not exclusively) in deliberative contexts that the ad
hominem has a place and should be regarded as an acceptable form of
argument. These are contexts in which there is a concern with matters
of policy and practice.”
Consequently, the context in which ad hominem occurs is an
essential factor in its evaluation.
Ad Hominem Examples with Explanation
The following examples of the argumentum ad hominem are
fairly straight-forward and suggested answers are explained. In each case, note
whether or not the character and/or circumstances of the individual being
depicted are germane to the claims made.
Ad Hominem Examples
- “Condoleezza Rice, former U.S. Secretary of State, responding to a
question about former Secretary of Defense Donald Rumsfeld's criticism of
her in his memoir: ‘Don can be a grumpy guy. We all know
that.’”
Comment: Rather than addressing Mr. Rumsfeld's criticism,
Ms. Rice ignores the question, imputes ill-temper to him, and
thereby commits the ad hominem fallacy.
- “[W]hen consultant/pundit/Democrat Hilary Rosen
commented on CNN that Ann Romney had never held a job (and
therefore was ill-suited to advise her husband on women's
employment concerns), … the Catholic League …
tweeted: ‘Lesbian Dem Hilary Rosen tells Ann Romney
she never worked a day in her life. Unlike Rosen, who had
to adopt kids, Ann raised 5 of her
own.’”
Comment: The allusion as to whether reared children are
adopted or not is not directly relevant in the context provided
for the purpose of deliberating women's employment concerns; thus,
the ad hominem fallacy occurs.
- “In America, the go-to guy on ADHD is Dr. Russell
Barkley … Barkley is on record saying that although
behavior therapy (behavior modification) can be a useful
supplementary treatment, no approach to ADHD has ever or is
probably ever going to completely replace pharmaceutical therapy.
In this regard it is significant to note that Barkley has had
ties to … the developer of the popular ADHD drug
Strattera.”
Comment: Normally the evidence for the truth or falsity of
the claim would be, strictly speaking, independent of Dr. Barkley's
past connections. However, Dr. Barkley's expertise cannot be
entirely disregarded since his testimony and experience is relevant
to the issue being discussed. Although biased innuendo is expressed
against Dr. Barkley in the original dialogue, this does not
necessarily result in an informal fallacy being committed since the
fact of much of Dr. Barkley's background is relevant. Nevertheless,
this consideration does not entirely justify Dr. Barkley assessment.
The best that can be said is that calling attention to Dr. Barkley's
association with the developer of an ADHD drug is uncharitable without
explaining what those ties are.
- ”President Trump is apparently convinced that his
son-in-law, who serves officially as a senior adviser, can fix
anything. Make that everything. … Kushner is
supposed to bring the mindset and practices of the business world
to the public sector. Given that his father went to jail for crimes
including tax evasion, and that his boss declared four businesses
bankruptcies, we can only hope Kushner looks far afield for role
models.”
Comment: The implicit argument is that Jared Kushner is
unlikely to be successful in his duties by the reasons that his
father is a felon and Donald Trump declared bankruptcies. Hence,
the ad hominem circumstantial fallacy (guilt by association)
is committed.
- “Once he [Benjamin F. Butler] was cross-questioning a
witness in his characteristic manner (with him politeness, or even
humanity, was out of the question). The judge interrupted to remind
him that the witness was a Harvard professor. ‘I know it, your
Honor,’ replied Butler; ‘we hanged one of them the
other day.’”
Comment: Mr. Butler argues that his rude cross examination
of a Harvard professor is unexceptional since a Harvard professor was
hanged recently — implying the witness' character is determinable
by association with other Harvard professors. Again, the ad
hominem circumstantial fallacy (guilt by association) is committed.
- ”[The New York Times] chronicled the enormous
benefits French citizens receive. Paid child care, free higher education,
free health care, a mandatory five weeks of paid vacation, monthly
government payments for each child … There comes a point
when ideology has to be put aside and what's good for the country
must be embraced. France is a selfish nation that is going down the
drain economically because the folks there want stuff and economics be
damned.”
Comment: Although the author of this passage, Mr. O'Reilly,
provides cogent reasons that government regulation and high taxes are
part of an unsustainable economy, assessing reasons for this conclusion
by attacking the character of the French people as wanting stuff, not
caring about economics, and being selfish, is not directly relevant:
ad hominem abusive.
- “Marvin Greenberg … spent many painful years in the
garment business. As he sees it, consumers willing to pay more for
better — and American — made clothes will remain a definite
minority. The vast shopping public demands basement-scraping prices on
two-for-one deals. Patriotism ends at the cash register. He's seen
it happen. ‘Back in the '50's there was a union protest in Fall
River (Mass.) about saving jobs, stopping imports,’ Greenberg
recalls. ‘People carrying signs were wearing imported
clothes.’”
Comment: Assuming an implicit argument, the conversational
implication is that Americans will not pay more for American apparel
good because even American garment workers themselves do not do so.
Also the reasoning is based on one group of workers to a conclusion
about all Americans and the fallacy of converse
accident is suggested. Nevertheless, the implicit argument qualifies
as a weak inductive argument rather than a clear fallacy.
- “The recent hype about global warming comes from the
Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Most of its members are
serious scientists. But reporters don't realize that those scientists,
like bird flu specialists, have every incentive to hype the risk. If
their computer models (which so far have been wrong) predict disaster,
they get attention and money. If they say, “I'm not sure,”
they get nothing.”
Comment: The ad hominem fallacy occurs since Mr. Stossel
ignores the empirical issues relating to global warming by claiming that
the conclusions of the scientists on the Intergovermental Panel are not as
much based on empirical evidence as they are based upon scientists
attempting to secure recognition and government funding.
- “Actress Salma Hayek has just been honoured at Equality
Now's ‘Make Equality Reality’ event, for
co-founding ‘Chime for Change’, which fights for women's
rights around the world. At the ceremony, which also honoured Gloria
Steinem, Hayek said: ’I am not a feminist. If men were going
through the things women are going through today, I would be fighting
for them with just as much passion. I believe in equality.‘
…
This is about the astonishing persistence of what I'd term small-f
feminist-woman. … The kind of woman, such as Hayek, who accepts
an award for helping women at an event also honouring Gloria Steinem
(Gloria Steinem!) and then has the graceless gall to use it as an
opportunity to announce that she isn't a feminist … You have to
wonder — what's with these women and their seemingly all-consuming
need to distance themselves from feminism? An unworthy thought crawls
through my brain: is this a man-pleasing exercise … Or does it go
yet deeper, darker, than that, into the realms of female self-hatred? …
While some may view this as an overreaction to some red carpet waffling,
to me, this is about small-f feminist-woman and how her unique brand of
self-hatred is taking far too long to die out.”
Comment: In addition to the verbal disagreement concerning the
meaning of feminism, Ms. Hayek is accused of either “man pleasing”
behavior or “female self-hatred” for her statement that she
is not a feminist. That restriction, in itself, poses a false dilemma. The
journalist commits an ad hominem abusive attack decorated
with a persuasive definition and the fallacy of complex question.
- “Norman Vincent Peale, a broadcast preacher and author of
The Power of Positive Thinking … said [Adlai] Stevenson
was unfit to be president because he was divorced. Stevenson said:
“I find the Apostle Paul appealing and the Apostle Peale
appalling.”
Comment: Mr. Peale and Mr. Stevenson both commit the fallacy of
ad hominem. Mr. Peale's personal attack turns on a
non causa pro causa (that being divorced
is a cause a being unfit for the presidency), and Mr. Stevenson's attack
turns on name-calling.
- Huey Long (Louisiana senator, 1935): “[L]et us take a
look at this NRA [Roosevelt's 1933 National Recovery Administration]
that they opened up around here two years ago. They had parades
and Fascist signs just as Hitler, and Mussolini. They started
the dictatorship here to regiment business and labor much more
than anyone did in Germany or Italy. The only difference was in
the sign. Italy's sign of he Fascist was a black shirt. Germany's
sign of the Fascist was a swastika. So in America they sidetracked
the Stars and Stripes, and the sign of the Blue Eagle was used
instead. And they proceeded with the
NRA.‘
Comment: Huey Long, politician and populist, poisons the well
by associating the Roosevelt administration with Fascists Hitler and
Mussolini in order to castigate the National Recovery Administration,
a New Deal agency. However, Long's analogue is not totally misguided
as in the same year this speech was broadcast, the Supreme Court
ruled the NRA unconstitutional since it violated the Constitution's
separation of powers.
- “Traditional empiricism insists that the social identity of
the observer is irrelevant to the ‘goodness’ of the results
of research. It is not supposed to make a difference to the explanatory
power, objectivity, and so on of the research's results if the researcher
or the community of scientists are white or black, Chinese or British,
rich or poor in social origin. But feminist empiricism argues that women
(or feminists, male and female) as a group are more likely than men
(non-feminists) as a group to produce claims unbiased by androcentrism,
and in that sense objective results of inquiry. It argues that the authors
of the favored social theories are not anonymous at all: they are clearly
men, and usually men of the dominant classes, races, and cultures. The
people who identify and define scientific problems leave their social
fingerprints on the problems and their favored solutions to
them.”
Comment: Certainly the claim that feminists as a group are
more likely than nonfeminists to be unbiased by androcentrism
(i.e., taking a masculine point of view) is trivially true.
Nonetheless, the conclusion drawn that feminists are more likely to
produce objective claims of inquiry than those produced by traditional
empiricism does not logically follow from this tautology. Further
evaluation of this argumentative passage depends to a great extent on
the context of the presentation and the background assumptions upon
which the argument is based. Nevertheless, the author argues that
feminists, unlike nonfeminists, are not androcentric and thus produce
claims which are objective results of inquiry. Since the adequacy of
scientific theories is measured in part by comparison of observed
results to expected results (an independent confirmation whose veracity
is not dependent upon whether or not the originators of the hypotheses
in question happen to be androcentric or gynocentric), the genetic
fallacy occurs in this quoted selected passage. Note that biased
selections of empirical observations in order to present specific
points of view, whether complied intentionally or unintentionally,
are precluded by traditional empiricism as improper scientific method.
Additionally, scientific theories and hypotheses are repeatedly
experimentally tested in accordance with procedural methods in
observation and experiment as part of the normal course of scientific
development. Thus, there is a justifiable “logical distinction
between the psychological processes which occur when a scientist
thinks of new ideas and the logical argument which exhibits the degree
to which those ideas are supported by the facts and other evidential
considerations.”
Some judge of authors' names, not work, and then
Nor praise nor blame the writings, but the men.
Alexander Pope, The Works of Alexander Pope,
vol. II, An Essay on Criticism (London: Longman
Brown, and Co. 1847), 357.
Notes
Note: Most text hyperlinks below reference exact page
“argumentum ad hominem, ad
feminam, lit. ‘the argument to a man, to a woman,’
refutation of a man's argument by an example drawn from his own
conduct.” Sir Walter Scott, Redgauntlet (London: Oxford University Press, 1912), 501.
In accordance with the proliferation of fallacies in the last fifty
years, the argumentum ad feminam in the sense of
attempting to discredit a woman's claim by appeal to her character
or circumstances may well become mainstream. If so, then recognition
might follow, as it has recently with the ad hominem, that the
ad feminam argument would not be necessarily
fallacious by definition.↩
It is sometimes shown that an opponent is precluded, by something in
his own special position, from the benefit of a principle appealed to
by him; a special mode of Refutation by Inconsistency, called the
Argumentum ad hominem.
Alexander Bain, English
Composition and Rhetoric (New York: D. Appleton, 1867) 240].
And, yet, for Bain, an argumentum ad hominem in this sense can
hold good but be fallacious because it relies on presumptive assumption
[Alexander Bain, The Minor Works of George Grote
(London: J. Murray, 1873), 357].
(6) Charles Sanders Pierce points out, “[An] argumentum
ad hominem [is] merely something a man is obliged by his personal interest
to admit” [Charles Saunders Peirce, “James's Psychology,”
in Writings of Charles S. Peirce vol. 8 (Bloomington: Indiana
University Press, 2010), 231]. So, for example, when discussing true
continuity in pure mathematics when he assumes a hypothesis independently
of its accordance with fact and attempts to avoid the argumentum ad
hominem that a conception of true continuity is not, for that reason,
a definite conception [Charles S. Pierce, “Topical Geometry,”
in The New Elements of Mathematics vol. 2, ed. Carolyn Eisele
(The Hague: Mouton Publishers, 1976), 483].
(7) Bertrand Russell defines the ad hominem argument as not
necessarily being fallacious since one “assume[s] premisses granted
by … opponents, and to show that, granting these premisses, it is
possible to deduce consequences which … opponents must deny.”
He gives the example of Zeno's arguments manifesting contradictions from
the supposition of change as ad hominem arguments which might be
valid or sophistic depending on “the tacit premissses” and
the person “at whom they were aimed” [Bertrand Russell,
Our
Knowledge of the External World (Chicago: Open Court, 1914), 168)].
(8)Jean-Jacques Robrieux who describes an “argumentum
ad hominem as argumentum ad concessis” as:
“á raisonner avec un interlocuteur ou un auditoire sur
la base de ses convictions propres, de ses préjugés,
et non sur celle des jugements universels,”
[I.e., “reasoning with an interlocutor or an audience on
the basis of his own convictions, his prejudices, and not on that of
universal judgments.”]
Jean-Jacques Robrieus, Éléments de Rhétorique et
d'Argumentation (Dunod, 1993), 143. ↩
”[I]t will surely furnish a fair argumentum
ad hominem against men, who reject that very thing in
Geometry which they admit in Logick. It will be a proper way to
abate the pride, and discredit the pretensions of these Logicians
and Metaphysicians, who insist upon clear ideas in points of
Mathematicks, if it be shewn that they do without them in their
own science.“ [italics deleted]The Minute Mathematician: or, the Free-Thinker No Just-Thinker,
by Philalethes Cantabrigiensis(London: Printed for T. Cooper, at
the Globe in Pater-Nolter-Row, 1735), 95. Also here: Trinity
College, Maths]
So the argumentum ad hominem alleged here is that the
method of Newton's calculation where the increments vanish is inconsistent
with his original assumption of the existence of increments in the
first place.
On the other hand, an example of argumentum ad hominem as
support for a consistency of belief is shown in this letter to Lord Mansfied
by Henry Home:
“[I]f a purchaser from an heir of provision, for example,
be secure, why not a purchaser from a gratuitous disponee [the
person to whom any property is legally conveyed]? What
objection should lie against the purchaser is not obvious,
considering that a purchaser even from a notour bankrupt is, in
the practice of the court of session, held to be secure; which
is at least a good argumentum ad hominem.”
[Henry Home, Principles
of Equity (Edinburgh: Printed for A. Millar, London,
and A. Kincaid & J. Bell, Edinburgh, 1760), 322.]
Henry Home here is arguing that since a purchaser from legitimate heir
is just as secure as a purchaser from a bankrupt person who failed to
discharge his debt, so likewise a purchaser from a receiver of a gift
of the subject of a deed should be just as secure as if he purchased
from a person whose property was legally conveyed. The reasoning is
consistent with past decisions of the course of sessions and so for this
reason, Home concludes, is a “good argumentum ad hominem.
(italics in original)”↩
“[W]e must be closed to compromise. No one need
try to convince me otherwise. The effort is futile; my conviction
is absolute.”
Charles M. Blow, “The
Death of Compassion,” The New York Times
(February 23, 2017)
A stance such as this one leads credence to the ad hominem
charge of bias since the author is so deeply entrenched in a
partisan issue that he refuses to consider any possible evidence
for an opposing view.
Even so, to some extent, everyone has deeply rooted fixed opinions:
“There is still another kind of prejudice similar to
that just considered — namely, the judgments which are born of
other minds and which, nevertheless, we come to appropriate as our
own. the reasons in which such judgments are grounded we have never
examined ourselves — possibly we could never understand even
if they were presented to us with elaborate explanation; and yet
the second-hand judgments cannot be eliminated wholly from our body
of knowledge without an incalculable loss.”
John Grier Hibben, “A Defence of Prejudice,” Scribner's Magazine
43 no. 1 (Jan. 1908), 118.]↩
“For the cause of any sensation, and the sensation itself, in
all the simple ideas of one sense, are two ideas; and two ideas so
different, and distant one from another, that no two can be more
so.”
[John Locke, An
Essay Concerning Human[e] Understanding (London:
Thomas Baffet, 1690), 199.] And in the late 1880s Henry Sidgwick writes,
“I cannot see how the mere ascertainment that a certain class of
apparently self-evident judgments has been caused in certain known and
determinate ways, can be in itself a valid ground for distrusting such
cognitions. I cannot even admit that those who affirm the truth of such
judgments are bound to show in their causes a tendency to make them
true.” Henry Sidgwick, The
Methods of Ethics: A Supplement to the Second
Edition (London: Macmillan and Co., 1884), 105.
Most current textbooks state a definition of the genetic fallacy similar
to this one:
“When someone gives an account of what led someone
(or a group) to a view and argues that since this (the account) is true,
the view is false, this is called the Genetic Fallacy.”
[J.D. Carney and R.K. Scheer. Fundamentals of Logic (New York:
Macmillan, 1964), 32.]
Even so, usually the claim is not that the view under consideration is
false — only that the claim has not been
proved.↩
“I do not wish to maintain that any strictly social
animal, if its intellectual faculties were to become as active and as
highly developed as in man, would acquire exactly the same moral sense
as ours. … If, for instance, to take an extreme case, men were
reared under precisely the same condition as hive-bees, there can hardly
be a doubt that our unmarried females would, like the worker-bees, think
it a sacred duty to kill their brothers, and mothers would strive to kill
their fertile daughters; and no one would think of interfering. Nevertheless,
the bee, or any other social animal, would gain in our supposed case, as it
appears to me, some feeling of right or wrong, or a conscience.”
Charles Darwin, The Descent of Man, vol I (London: John Murray,
1871), 73. ↩
“Questions about the genesis of an idea (belief, concept
theory) is one thing (an empirical question for psychology,
sociology or history), whereas questions about the validity and
justification of an idea is a different question (a normative
question for logic and epistemology).” Kitchener,
285.“
He cites this distinction as one kind of the fact-norm distinction
which “provides the underlying rationale of the notorious
genetic fallacy.” Further, he concludes, “What is
clearly being ruled out, thererfore is the very possibility that
a question about the ‘genesis’ of an idea could have
some relevance towards evaluating its epistemic adequacy.”
(Kitchener, 286).↩
Readings: Ad Hominem
Andrew Aberden, “Commentary
on Patrick Bondy, ‘Bias in Legitimate Ad Hominem
Arguments,’” OSSA Conference Archive 11, 7 (2016),
1-5.
Scott Aikin, “Tu
Quoque Arguments and the Significance of Hypocrisy,”
Informal Logic 28 no. 2 (June 2008), 155-169. doi: 10.22329/il.v28i2.543
E. M. Barthand and J.L. Martens. “Argumentum
Ad Hominem: From Chaos to Formal Dialectic,” Logique &
Analyse 20 no. 77-78 (March-June 1977), 76-96.
Heather Battaly, “Attacking
Character: Ad Hominem Argument and Virtue Epistemology,”
Informal Logic 30 no.4 (2010), 361-390. doi: 10.22329/il.v30i4.2964.
Patrick Bondy, “Bias
in Legitimate Ad Hominem Arguments,” In
Argumentation, Objectivity, and Bias. Eds. P.
Bondy and L. Benacquista OSSA (May 2016), 1-8.
Patrick Bondy, “Virtues,
Evidence, and Ad Hominem Arguments,” Informal
Logic 35 no. 4 (2015), 450-466. doi:
10.22329/il.v35i4.4330.
Alan Brinton, “A
Rhetorical View of the Ad Hominem,”
Australasian Journal of Philosophy 63 no. 1 (March 1985),
50-63. doi:
10.1080/00048408512341681. (paywall)
Alan Brinton, “The Ad Hominem,” Fallacies:
Classical and Contemporary Readings. Eds. Hans V. Hansen and
Robert C. Pinto. (University Park, PA: Pennsylvania State University,
1995), 213-222. (preview)
Maarten Boudry and Fabio Paglieri and Massimo Pigliucci.
“The
Fake, the Flimsy, and the Fallacious: Demarcating Arguments in Real
Life,” Maarten Boudry Google Scholar. https://sites.google.com/site/maartenboudry/teksten-1/fake. Argumentation
29 no. 4 (November 2015), 431-456. doi:
10.1007/s10503-015-9359-1
Katarzna Budzynska and Chris Reed. “The Structure of Ad
Hominem Dialogues,” Computational Models of Arguments
Series: Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence and Applications vol.245
(2012), 410-421. doi:
10.3233/978-1-61499-111-3-410
James Cargile, “Two Fallacies,” Logos & Episteme 1 no. 2 (2010), 257-268. doi: 10.5840/logos-episteme2010124
Graciela Marta Chichi, “The
Greek Roots of the Ad Hominem-Argument,”
Argumentation 16 no. 3 (September 2002), 333-348. doi: 10.1023/A:1019967112062
(paywall)
Margaret A. Crouch, “A ‘Limited’Defense
of the Genetic Fallacy,” Metaphilosophy 24 no 3
(July 1993), 227-240. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-9973.1993.tb00900.x (paywall)
Stephen De Wijze “Complexity, Relevance and Character:
Problems with Teaching the Ad Hominem Fallacy,”
Educational Philosophy and Theory 35 (2003),
31-56. doi:
10.1111/1469-5812.00004 (paywall)
S. Morris.Engel, “The Five Forms of the Ad Hominem
Fallacy,” Inquiry 14 no. 1 (Autumn 1994):
19-36. doi:10.5840/inquiryctnews199414123 (paywall)
T. A. Goudge, “The
Genetic Fallacy,” Synthese 13 no. 1 (1961), 41-48.
doi:
10.1007/BF00485935 (paywall)
Ulrike Hahn and Mike Oaksford, Adam J.L. Harris. “Testimony and
Argument: A Bayesian Perspective,” Bayesian
Argumentation ed. Frank Zenker (Dordrecht: Springer, 2013), 15-38. doi:
10.1007/978-94-007-5357-0_2
Norwood Russell Hansen, “The Irrelevance of History of
Science to Philosophy of Science,” The Journal of
Philosophy 59 no. 21 (Oct. 1962), 574-586. doi:
10.2307/2023279 (paywall)
David Hitchcock, “Is There an Argumentum ad Hominem
Fallacy?,” in On Reasoning and Argument. Ed. David
Hitchcock (Springer International, 2017), 409-419.
doi:
10.1007/978-3-319-53562-3_26 (preview)
David Hitchcock, “The Pragma-Dialectical Analysis of
the Ad Hominem Fallacy,” In Considering
Pragma-Dialectics.. Eds. Peter Houtlosser and Agnès
van Rees. (Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaus Associates, 2006),
109-119. (preview)
David Hitchcock, “Why
There is No Argumentum Ad Hominem
Fallacy,” In Proceedings of the Sixth Conference of the
International Society for the Study of Argumentation. Eds.
F.H. van Eemeren and B. Garssen. 1 (Amsterdam: Sic Sat, 2007),
615-620.
John Hoaglund, “Argumentum ad Hominem: Aut Bonum aut Malum?,”
Informal Logic 4 no. 3 (July 1981), 7-9. doi: 10.22329/il.v4i3.2773
Gary James Jason, “Is There a Case for Ad Hominem
Arguments?,” Australasian Journal of Philosophy
62 no. 2 (1984), 182-185. doi: 10.1080/00048408412341381 (paywall)
Christopher M. Johnson, “Reconsidering the Ad
Hominem,” Philosophy 84 no. 2 (April 2009), 251-266.
doi:
10.1017/S0031819109000217 (paywall)
H.W. Johnstone, Jr., “Philosophy and Argumentum ad
Hominem,” Journal of Philosophy 49 no. 15
(17 July 1952), 489-498. doi:
10.2307/2021667 (paywall)
Kevin C. Klement, “When Is Genetic Reasoning Not
Fallacious,” Argumentation 16 no. 4 (December 2002),
383-400. doi:
10.1023/A:1021132731699
Erik C.W. Krabbe and Douglas Walton, “It's
All Very Well for You to Talk! Situationally Disqualifying Ad
Hominem Attacks,” Informal Logic 15 no. 2 (1993),
79-91. doi:
10.22329/il.v15i2.2475"
T. Z. Lavine, “Reflections on the Genetic Fallacy,” Social
Research. 29 no. 3 (Autumn 1962), 321-336. (paywall)
Stephen Law, “Thinking
Tools: The Genetic Fallacy,” Think 5
no. 13 (June 2006), 23-24. doi:
10.1017/S1477175600001500 (paywall)
P.T. Mackenzie, “Ad
Hominem and Ad Verecundiam,”
Informal Logic 3 no. 3 (1980), 9-11. doi:
10.22329/il.v3i3.2792
John. McMurtry, “The
Argumentum Ad Adversarium,” Informal Logic
8 no. 1 (Winter, 1986), 27-36. doi:
10.22329/il.v8i1.2678"
Moti Mizrahi, “Take
My Advice — I Am Not Following It: Ad Hominem Arguments
as Legitimate Rebuttals to Appeals to Authority,” Informal
Logic 30 no. 4 (2010): 435-456. doi: 10.22329/il.v30i4.2990
B. Meuffels, and F.H. van Eemeren, “Ordinary
Arguers' Judgments on Ad Hominem Fallacies,”
Advances in Pragma-dialectics. Ed. F.H. van Eemeren
(Amsterdam: Sic Sat/Vale Press, 2002), 45-64. (no preview)
Gabriël Nuchelmans, “On the Fourfold Root
of The Argumentum Ad Hominem,” in E.C.W. Krabe, R.J. Dalitz
and P. Smith (eds.), Empirical Logic and Public Debate
(Amsterdam-Atlanta, Rodopi,1993), 37-47.
Jon Pashman, “Is the Genetic Fallacy a Fallacy?,”
The Southern Journal of Philosophy 8 no. 1 (Spring 1970),
57-62. doi: 10.1111/j.2041-6962.1970
H.J. Plug, “Parrying Ad-HominemArguments in Parliamentary Debates.” Proceedings of the 7th Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation. Eds. F.H. van Eemeren, et al. (Amsterdam: Rozenberg/Sic Sat.), 1538-1546. https://pure.uva.nl/ws/files/1830340/128194_138_Plug.pdf
Yvone Raley, “Character Attacks: How to Properly Apply the Ad Hominem.” Scientific American Mind. https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/character-attack/
van Eemeren, Frans H. and Rob Grootendorst. “Argumentum
Ad Hominem: A Pragma-Dialectical Case in Point.” In Fallacies: Classical and Contemporary Readings. Eds. Hans V. Hansen and Robert C. Pinto (University Park PA: Pennsylvania State University Press: 1995), 223-228.
Frans H. van Eemeren and Rob Grootendorst. “Relevance
Reviewed: The Case of Argumentum ad Hominem,”
Argumentation 6 no. 2 (May 1992), 141-159. doi: 10.1007/BF00154322
Douglas N. Walton, “The
Ad Hominem Argument as an Informal Fallacy.”
Argumentation 1 no.3 (1987), 320. doi: 10.1007/bf00136781
Douglas N. Walton, Ad Hominem Arguments, (Tuscalooosa, AL: University
of Alabama Press, 1998). (preview)
Douglas N. Walton, “Argumentation Schemes and Historical Origins of the Circumstantial Ad Hominem Argument.” Argumentation 18 no. 3 (September 2004), 359-368. doi: 10.1023/B:ARGU.0000046706.45919.83
Douglas N. Walton, “The Ad Hominem Argument as an Informal Fallacy,”
Argumentation 1 (1987), 317-331. doi:10.1007/BF00136781
Douglas N. Walton, Character Evidence: An Abductive Theory
(Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer, 2006). doi: 10.1007/1-4020-4943-9
Douglas N. Walton, “Formalization of the Ad Hominem Argumentation Scheme,” Journal of Applied Logic 8 no. 1 (March 2010), 1-21. doi: 10.1016/j.jal.2008.07.002
Douglas N. Walton, “On a Razor's Edge: Evaluating Arguments from Expert Opinion,” Argument & Computation 5 no. 2/3 (2014), 139-159. doi: 10.1080/19462166.2013.858183
Douglas N. Walton, “Poisoning the Well,” Argumentation 20 no. 3 (September 2006), 273-307. doi: 10.1007/s10503-006-9013-z
Douglas N. Walton, “Searching for the Roots of the Circumstantial
Ad Hominem” Argumentation 15 no. 2 (May 2001), 207-221. doi: 10.1023/A:1011120100277
Douglas N. Walton, “Witness Testimony as Argumentation.” Witness Testimony Evidence (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2007), 12-61. doi:10.1017/CBO9780511619533.002
A.C. Ward, “The Value of Genetic Fallacies.”
Informal Logic 30 no. 1 (2010), 1-30. doi:10.22329/il.v30i1.1237
Wikipedia contributors, ”Ad hominem,” Wikipedia
(accessed June 23, 2020).
John Woods, “Lightening Up on the Ad Hominem.”
Informal Logic 27 no. 1 (2007), 109-134. 10.22329/il.v27i1.467
Audrey Yap, “Ad Hominem Fallacies, Bias, and Testimony,”
Argumentation 27 (2013), 97-109. doi: 10.1007/s10503-011-9260-5.
|
|